fundamental principles of the metaphysic of morals-第21章
按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!
although they have not been done。 However; this freedom is not a
conception of experience; nor can it be so; since it still remains;
even though experience shows the contrary of what on supposition of
freedom are conceived as its necessary consequences。 On the other side
it is equally necessary that everything that takes place should be
fixedly determined according to laws of nature。 This necessity of
nature is likewise not an empirical conception; just for this
reason; that it involves the motion of necessity and consequently of a
priori cognition。 But this conception of a system of nature is
confirmed by experience; and it must even be inevitably presupposed if
experience itself is to be possible; that is; a connected knowledge of
the objects of sense resting on general laws。 Therefore freedom is
only an idea of reason; and its objective reality in itself is
doubtful; while nature is a concept of the understanding which proves;
and must necessarily prove; its reality in examples of experience。
There arises from this a dialectic of reason; since the freedom
attributed to the will appears to contradict the necessity of
nature; and placed between these two ways reason for speculative
purposes finds the road of physical necessity much more beaten and
more appropriate than that of freedom; yet for practical purposes
the narrow footpath of freedom is the only one on which it is possible
to make use of reason in our conduct; hence it is just as impossible
for the subtlest philosophy as for the commonest reason of men to
argue away freedom。 Philosophy must then assume that no real
contradiction will be found between freedom and physical necessity
of the same human actions; for it cannot give up the conception of
nature any more than that of freedom。
Nevertheless; even though we should never be able to comprehend
how freedom is possible; we must at least remove this apparent
contradiction in a convincing manner。 For if the thought of freedom
contradicts either itself or nature; which is equally necessary; it
must in competition with physical necessity be entirely given up。
It would; however; be impossible to escape this contradiction if the
thinking subject; which seems to itself free; conceived itself in
the same sense or in the very same relation when it calls itself
free as when in respect of the same action it assumes itself to be
subject to the law of nature。 Hence it is an indispensable problem
of speculative philosophy to show that its illusion respecting the
contradiction rests on this; that we think of man in a different sense
and relation when we call him free and when we regard him as subject
to the laws of nature as being part and parcel of nature。 It must
therefore show that not only can both these very well co…exist; but
that both must be thought as necessarily united in the same subject;
since otherwise no reason could be given why we should burden reason
with an idea which; though it may possibly without contradiction be
reconciled with another that is sufficiently established; yet
entangles us in a perplexity which sorely embarrasses reason in its
theoretic employment。 This duty; however; belongs only to
speculative philosophy。 The philosopher then has no option whether
he will remove the apparent contradiction or leave it untouched; for
in the latter case the theory respecting this would be bonum vacans;
into the possession of which the fatalist would have a right to
enter and chase all morality out of its supposed domain as occupying
it without title。
We cannot however as yet say that we are touching the bounds of
practical philosophy。 For the settlement of that controversy does
not belong to it; it only demands from speculative reason that it
should put an end to the discord in which it entangles itself in
theoretical questions; so that practical reason may have rest and
security from external attacks which might make the ground debatable
on which it desires to build。
The claims to freedom of will made even by common reason are founded
on the consciousness and the admitted supposition that reason is
independent of merely subjectively determined causes which together
constitute what belongs to sensation only and which consequently
come under the general designation of sensibility。 Man considering
himself in this way as an intelligence places himself thereby in a
different order of things and in a relation to determining grounds
of a wholly different kind when on the one hand he thinks of himself
as an intelligence endowed with a will; and consequently with
causality; and when on the other he perceives himself as a
phenomenon in the world of sense (as he really is also); and affirms
that his causality is subject to external determination according to
laws of nature。 Now he soon becomes aware that both can hold good;
nay; must hold good at the same time。 For there is not the smallest
contradiction in saying that a thing in appearance (belonging to the
world of sense) is subject to certain laws; of which the very same
as a thing or being in itself is independent; and that he must
conceive and think of himself in this twofold way; rests as to the
first on the consciousness of himself as an object affected through
the senses; and as to the second on the consciousness of himself as an
intelligence; i。e。; as independent on sensible impressions in the
employment of his reason (in other words as belonging to the world
of understanding)。
Hence it comes to pass that man claims the possession of a will
which takes no account of anything that comes under the head of
desires and inclinations and; on the contrary; conceives actions as
possible to him; nay; even as necessary which can only be done by
disregarding all desires and sensible inclinations。 The causality of
such actions lies in him as an intelligence and in the laws of effects
and actions 'which depend' on the principles of an intelligible world;
of which indeed he knows nothing more than that in it pure reason
alone independent of sensibility gives the law; moreover since it is
only in that world; as an intelligence; that he is his proper self
(being as man only the appearance of himself); those laws apply to him
directly and categorically; so that the incitements of inclinations
and appetites (in other words the whole nature of the world of
sense) cannot impair the laws of his volition as an intelligence。 Nay;
he does not even hold himself responsible for the former or ascribe
them to his proper self; i。e。; his will: he only ascribes to his
will any indulgence which he might yield them if he allowed them to
influence his maxims to the prejudice of the rational laws of the
will。
When practical reason thinks itself into a world of understanding;
it does not thereby transcend its own limits; as it would if it
tried to enter it by intuition or sensation。 The former is only a
negative thought in respect of the world of sense; which does not give
any laws to reason in determining the will and is positive only in
this single point that this freedom as a negative characteristic is at
the same time conjoined with a (positive) faculty and even with a
causality of reason; which we designate a will; namely a faculty of so
acting that the principle of the actions shall conform to the
essential character of a rational motive; i。e。; the condition that the
maxim have universal validity as a law。 But were it to borrow an
object of will; that is; a motive; from the world of understanding;
then it would overstep its bounds and pretend to be acquainted with
something of which it knows nothing。 The conception of a world of
the understanding is then only a point of view which reason finds
itself compelled to take outside the appearances in order to
conceive itself as practical; which would not be possible if the
influences of the sensibility had a determining power on man; but
which is necessary unless he is to be denied the