fundamental principles of the metaphysic of morals-第16章
按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!
but the subject of all possible ends; since this is also the subject
of a possible absolutely good will; for such a will cannot without
contradiction be postponed to any other object。 The principle: 〃So act
in regard to every rational being (thyself and others); that he may
always have place in thy maxim as an end in himself;〃 is accordingly
essentially identical with this other: 〃Act upon a maxim which; at the
same time; involves its own universal validity for every rational
being。〃 For that in using means for every end I should limit my
maxim by the condition of its holding good as a law for every subject;
this comes to the same thing as that the fundamental principle of
all maxims of action must be that the subject of all ends; i。e。; the
rational being himself; be never employed merely as means; but as
the supreme condition restricting the use of all means; that is in
every case as an end likewise。
It follows incontestably that; to whatever laws any rational being
may be subject; he being an end in himself must be able to regard
himself as also legislating universally in respect of these same laws;
since it is just this fitness of his maxims for universal
legislation that distinguishes him as an end in himself; also it
follows that this implies his dignity (prerogative) above all mere
physical beings; that he must always take his maxims from the point of
view which regards himself and; likewise; every other rational being
as law…giving beings (on which account they are called persons)。 In
this way a world of rational beings (mundus intelligibilis) is
possible as a kingdom of ends; and this by virtue of the legislation
proper to all persons as members。 Therefore every rational being
must so act as if he were by his maxims in every case a legislating
member in the universal kingdom of ends。 The formal principle of these
maxims is: 〃So act as if thy maxim were to serve likewise as the
universal law (of all rational beings)。〃 A kingdom of ends is thus
only possible on the analogy of a kingdom of nature; the former
however only by maxims; that is self…imposed rules; the latter only by
the laws of efficient causes acting under necessitation from
without。 Nevertheless; although the system of nature is looked upon as
a machine; yet so far as it has reference to rational beings as its
ends; it is given on this account the name of a kingdom of nature。 Now
such a kingdom of ends would be actually realized by means of maxims
conforming to the canon which the categorical imperative prescribes to
all rational beings; if they were universally followed。 But although a
rational being; even if he punctually follows this maxim himself;
cannot reckon upon all others being therefore true to the same; nor
expect that the kingdom of nature and its orderly arrangements shall
be in harmony with him as a fitting member; so as to form a kingdom of
ends to which he himself contributes; that is to say; that it shall
favour his expectation of happiness; still that law: 〃Act according to
the maxims of a member of a merely possible kingdom of ends
legislating in it universally;〃 remains in its full force; inasmuch as
it commands categorically。 And it is just in this that the paradox
lies; that the mere dignity of man as a rational creature; without any
other end or advantage to be attained thereby; in other words; respect
for a mere idea; should yet serve as an inflexible precept of the
will; and that it is precisely in this independence of the maxim on
all such springs of action that its sublimity consists; and it is this
that makes every rational subject worthy to be a legislative member in
the kingdom of ends: for otherwise he would have to be conceived
only as subject to the physical law of his wants。 And although we
should suppose the kingdom of nature and the kingdom of ends to be
united under one sovereign; so that the latter kingdom thereby
ceased to be a mere idea and acquired true reality; then it would no
doubt gain the accession of a strong spring; but by no means any
increase of its intrinsic worth。 For this sole absolute lawgiver must;
notwithstanding this; be always conceived as estimating the worth of
rational beings only by their disinterested behaviour; as prescribed
to themselves from that idea 'the dignity of man' alone。 The essence
of things is not altered by their external relations; and that
which; abstracting from these; alone constitutes the absolute worth of
man; is also that by which he must be judged; whoever the judge may
be; and even by the Supreme Being。 Morality; then; is the relation
of actions to the relation of actions will; that is; to the autonomy
of potential universal legislation by its maxims。 An action that is
consistent with the autonomy of the will is permitted; one that does
not agree therewith is forbidden。 A will whose maxims necessarily
coincide with the laws of autonomy is a holy will; good absolutely。
The dependence of a will not absolutely good on the principle of
autonomy (moral necessitation) is obligation。 This; then; cannot be
applied to a holy being。 The objective necessity of actions from
obligation is called duty。
From what has just been said; it is easy to see how it happens that;
although the conception of duty implies subjection to the law; we
yet ascribe a certain dignity and sublimity to the person who
fulfils all his duties。 There is not; indeed; any sublimity in him; so
far as he is subject to the moral law; but inasmuch as in regard to
that very law he is likewise a legislator; and on that account alone
subject to it; he has sublimity。 We have also shown above that neither
fear nor inclination; but simply respect for the law; is the spring
which can give actions a moral worth。 Our own will; so far as we
suppose it to act only under the condition that its maxims are
potentially universal laws; this ideal will which is possible to us is
the proper object of respect; and the dignity of humanity consists
just in this capacity of being universally legislative; though with
the condition that it is itself subject to this same legislation。
The Autonomy of the Will as the Supreme Principle of Morality
Autonomy of the will is that property of it by which it is a law
to itself (independently of any property of the objects of
volition)。 The principle of autonomy then is: 〃Always so to choose
that the same volition shall comprehend the maxims of our choice as
a universal law。〃 We cannot prove that this practical rule is an
imperative; i。e。; that the will of every rational being is necessarily
bound to it as a condition; by a mere analysis of the conceptions
which occur in it; since it is a synthetical proposition; we must
advance beyond the cognition of the objects to a critical
examination of the subject; that is; of the pure practical reason; for
this synthetic proposition which commands apodeictically must be
capable of being cognized wholly a priori。 This matter; however;
does not belong to the present section。 But that the principle of
autonomy in question is the sole principle of morals can be readily
shown by mere analysis of the conceptions of morality。 For by this
analysis we find that its principle must be a categorical imperative
and that what this commands is neither more nor less than this very
autonomy。
Heteronomy of the Will as the Source of all spurious Principles
of Morality
If the will seeks the law which is to determine it anywhere else
than in the fitness of its maxims to be universal laws of its own
dictation; consequently if it goes out of itself and seeks this law in
the character of any of its objects; there always results
heteronomy。 The will in that case does not give itself the law; but it
is given by the object through its relation to the will。 This
relation; whether it rests on inclination or on conceptions of reason;
only admits of hypothetical imperatives: 〃I ought to do somet