the critique of pure reason-第159章
按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!
technically; that is; from observation of the similarity existing
between different objects; and the purely contingent use we make of
our knowledge in concreto with reference to all kinds of arbitrary
external aims; its constitution must be framed on architectonical
principles; that is; its parts must be shown to possess an essential
affinity; and be capable of being deduced from one supreme and
internal aim or end; which forms the condition of the possibility of
the scientific whole。 The schema of a science must give a priori the
plan of it (monogramma); and the division of the whole into parts;
in conformity with the idea of the science; and it must also
distinguish this whole from all others; according to certain
understood principles。
No one will attempt to construct a science; unless he have some idea
to rest on as a proper basis。 But; in the elaboration of the
science; he finds that the schema; nay; even the definition which he
at first gave of the science; rarely corresponds with his idea; for
this idea lies; like a germ; in our reason; its parts undeveloped
and hid even from microscopical observation。 For this reason; we ought
to explain and define sciences; not according to the description which
the originator gives of them; but according to the idea which we
find based in reason itself; and which is suggested by the natural
unity of the parts of the science already accumulated。 For it will
of ten be found that the originator of a science and even his latest
successors remain attached to an erroneous idea; which they cannot
render clear to themselves; and that they thus fail in determining the
true content; the articulation or systematic unity; and the limits
of their science。
It is unfortunate that; only after having occupied ourselves for a
long time in the collection of materials; under the guidance of an
idea which lies undeveloped in the mind; but not according to any
definite plan of arrangement… nay; only after we have spent much
time and labour in the technical disposition of our materials; does it
become possible to view the idea of a science in a clear light; and to
project; according to architectonical principles; a plan of the whole;
in accordance with the aims of reason。 Systems seem; like certain
worms; to be formed by a kind of generatio aequivoca… by the mere
confluence of conceptions; and to gain completeness only with the
progress of time。 But the schema or germ of all lies in reason; and
thus is not only every system organized according to its own idea; but
all are united into one grand system of human knowledge; of which they
form members。 For this reason; it is possible to frame an
architectonic of all human cognition; the formation of which; at the
present time; considering the immense materials collected or to be
found in the ruins of old systems; would not indeed be very difficult。
Our purpose at present is merely to sketch the plan of the
architectonic of all cognition given by pure reason; and we begin from
the point where the main root of human knowledge divides into two; one
of which is reason。 By reason I understand here the whole higher
faculty of cognition; the rational being placed in contradistinction
to the empirical。
If I make complete abstraction of the content of cognition;
objectively considered; all cognition is; from a subjective point of
view; either historical or rational。 Historical cognition is
cognitio ex datis; rational; cognitio ex principiis。 Whatever may be
the original source of a cognition; it is; in relation to the person
who possesses it; merely historical; if he knows only what has been
given him from another quarter; whether that knowledge was
communicated by direct experience or by instruction。 Thus the Person
who has learned a system of philosophy… say the Wolfian… although he
has a perfect knowledge of all the principles; definitions; and
arguments in that philosophy; as well as of the divisions that have
been made of the system; possesses really no more than an historical
knowledge of the Wolfian system; he knows only what has been told him;
his judgements are only those which he has received from his teachers。
Dispute the validity of a definition; and he is completely at a loss
to find another。 He has formed his mind on another's; but the
imitative faculty is not the productive。 His knowledge has not been
drawn from reason; and although; objectively considered; it is
rational knowledge; subjectively; it is merely historical。 He has
learned this or that philosophy and is merely a plaster cast of a
living man。 Rational cognitions which are objective; that is; which
have their source in reason; can be so termed from a subjective
point of view; only when they have been drawn by the individual
himself from the sources of reason; that is; from principles; and it
is in this way alone that criticism; or even the rejection of what has
been already learned; can spring up in the mind。
All rational cognition is; again; based either on conceptions; or on
the construction of conceptions。 The former is termed philosophical;
the latter mathematical。 I have already shown the essential difference
of these two methods of cognition in the first chapter。 A cognition
may be objectively philosophical and subjectively historical… as is
the case with the majority of scholars and those who cannot look
beyond the limits of their system; and who remain in a state of
pupilage all their lives。 But it is remarkable that mathematical
knowledge; when committed to memory; is valid; from the subjective
point of view; as rational knowledge also; and that the same
distinction cannot be drawn here as in the case of philosophical
cognition。 The reason is that the only way of arriving at this
knowledge is through the essential principles of reason; and thus it
is always certain and indisputable; because reason is employed in
concreto… but at the same time a priori… that is; in pure and;
therefore; infallible intuition; and thus all causes of illusion and
error are excluded。 Of all the a priori sciences of reason; therefore;
mathematics alone can be learned。 Philosophy… unless it be in an
historical manner… cannot be learned; we can at most learn to
philosophize。
Philosophy is the system of all philosophical cognition。 We must use
this term in an objective sense; if we understand by it the
archetype of all attempts at philosophizing; and the standard by which
all subjective philosophies are to be judged。 In this sense;
philosophy is merely the idea of a possible science; which does not
exist in concreto; but to which we endeavour in various ways to
approximate; until we have discovered the right path to pursue… a path
overgrown by the errors and illusions of sense… and the image we
have hitherto tried in vain to shape has become a perfect copy of
the great prototype。 Until that time; we cannot learn philosophy… it
does not exist; if it does; where is it; who possesses it; and how
shall we know it? We can only learn to philosophize; in other words;
we can only exercise our powers of reasoning in accordance with
general principles; retaining at the same time; the right of
investigating the sources of these principles; of testing; and even of
rejecting them。
Until then; our conception of philosophy is only a scholastic
conception… a conception; that is; of a system of cognition which we
are trying to elaborate into a science; all that we at present know
being the systematic unity of this cognition; and consequently the
logical completeness of the cognition for the desired end。 But there
is also a cosmical conception (conceptus cosmicus) of philosophy;
which has always formed the true basis of this term; especially when
philosophy was personified and presented to us in the ideal of a
philosopher。 In this view philosophy is the science of the relation of
all cognition to the ultimate and essential aims of human reason
(teleologia rationis