the critique of pure reason-第141章
按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!
contain some of the elements requisite to form a complete
definition。 If a conception could not be employed in reasoning
before it had been defined; it would fare ill with all philosophical
thought。 But; as incompletely defined conceptions may always be
employed without detriment to truth; so far as our analysis of the
elements contained in them proceeds; imperfect definitions; that is;
propositions which are properly not definitions; but merely
approximations thereto; may be used with great advantage。 In
mathematics; definition belongs ad esse; in philosophy ad melius esse。
It is a difficult task to construct a proper definition。 Jurists are
still without a complete definition of the idea of right。
(b) Mathematical definitions cannot be erroneous。 For the conception
is given only in and through the definition; and thus it contains only
what has been cogitated in the definition。 But although a definition
cannot be incorrect; as regards its content; an error may sometimes;
although seldom; creep into the form。 This error consists in a want of
precision。 Thus the common definition of a circle… that it is a curved
line; every point in which is equally distant from another point
called the centre… is faulty; from the fact that the determination
indicated by the word curved is superfluous。 For there ought to be a
particular theorem; which may be easily proved from the definition; to
the effect that every line; which has all its points at equal
distances from another point; must be a curved line… that is; that not
even the smallest part of it can be straight。 Analytical
definitions; on the other hand; may be erroneous in many respects;
either by the introduction of signs which do not actually exist in the
conception; or by wanting in that completeness which forms the
essential of a definition。 In the latter case; the definition is
necessarily defective; because we can never be fully certain of the
completeness of our analysis。 For these reasons; the method of
definition employed in mathematics cannot be imitated in philosophy。
2。 Of Axioms。 These; in so far as they are immediately certain;
are a priori synthetical principles。 Now; one conception cannot be
connected synthetically and yet immediately with another; because;
if we wish to proceed out of and beyond a conception; a third
mediating cognition is necessary。 And; as philosophy is a cognition of
reason by the aid of conceptions alone; there is to be found in it
no principle which deserves to be called an axiom。 Mathematics; on the
other hand; may possess axioms; because it can always connect the
predicates of an object a priori; and without any mediating term; by
means of the construction of conceptions in intuition。 Such is the
case with the proposition: Three points can always lie in a plane。
On the other hand; no synthetical principle which is based upon
conceptions; can ever be immediately certain (for example; the
proposition: Everything that happens has a cause); because I require a
mediating term to connect the two conceptions of event and cause…
namely; the condition of time…determination in an experience; and I
cannot cognize any such principle immediately and from conceptions
alone。 Discursive principles are; accordingly; very different from
intuitive principles or axioms。 The former always require deduction;
which in the case of the latter may be altogether dispensed with。
Axioms are; for this reason; always self…evident; while
philosophical principles; whatever may be the degree of certainty they
possess; cannot lay any claim to such a distinction。 No synthetical
proposition of pure transcendental reason can be so evident; as is
often rashly enough declared; as the statement; twice two are four。 It
is true that in the Analytic I introduced into the list of
principles of the pure understanding; certain axioms of intuition; but
the principle there discussed was not itself an axiom; but served
merely to present the principle of the possibility of axioms in
general; while it was really nothing more than a principle based
upon conceptions。 For it is one part of the duty of transcendental
philosophy to establish the possibility of mathematics itself。
Philosophy possesses; then; no axioms; and has no right to impose
its a priori principles upon thought; until it has established their
authority and validity by a thoroughgoing deduction。
3。 Of Demonstrations。 Only an apodeictic proof; based upon
intuition; can be termed a demonstration。 Experience teaches us what
is; but it cannot convince us that it might not have been otherwise。
Hence a proof upon empirical grounds cannot be apodeictic。 A priori
conceptions; in discursive cognition; can never produce intuitive
certainty or evidence; however certain the judgement they present
may be。 Mathematics alone; therefore; contains demonstrations; because
it does not deduce its cognition from conceptions; but from the
construction of conceptions; that is; from intuition; which can be
given a priori in accordance with conceptions。 The method of
algebra; in equations; from which the correct answer is deduced by
reduction; is a kind of construction… not geometrical; but by symbols…
in which all conceptions; especially those of the relations of
quantities; are represented in intuition by signs; and thus the
conclusions in that science are secured from errors by the fact that
every proof is submitted to ocular evidence。 Philosophical cognition
does not possess this advantage; it being required to consider the
general always in abstracto (by means of conceptions); while
mathematics can always consider it in concreto (in an individual
intuition); and at the same time by means of a priori
representation; whereby all errors are rendered manifest to the
senses。 The former… discursive proofs… ought to be termed acroamatic
proofs; rather than demonstrations; as only words are employed in
them; while demonstrations proper; as the term itself indicates;
always require a reference to the intuition of the object。
It follows from all these considerations that it is not consonant
with the nature of philosophy; especially in the sphere of pure
reason; to employ the dogmatical method; and to adorn itself with
the titles and insignia of mathematical science。 It does not belong to
that order; and can only hope for a fraternal union with that science。
Its attempts at mathematical evidence are vain pretensions; which
can only keep it back from its true aim; which is to detect the
illusory procedure of reason when transgressing its proper limits; and
by fully explaining and analysing our conceptions; to conduct us
from the dim regions of speculation to the clear region of modest
self…knowledge。 Reason must not; therefore; in its transcendental
endeavours; look forward with such confidence; as if the path it is
pursuing led straight to its aim; nor reckon with such security upon
its premisses; as to consider it unnecessary to take a step back; or
to keep a strict watch for errors; which; overlooked in the
principles; may be detected in the arguments themselves… in which case
it may be requisite either to determine these principles with
greater strictness; or to change them entirely。
I divide all apodeictic propositions; whether demonstrable or
immediately certain; into dogmata and mathemata。 A direct
synthetical proposition; based on conceptions; is a dogma; a
proposition of the same kind; based on the construction of
conceptions; is a mathema。 Analytical judgements do not teach us any
more about an object than what was contained in the conception we
had of it; because they do not extend our cognition beyond our
conception of an object; they merely elucidate the conception。 They
cannot therefore be with propriety termed dogmas。 Of the two kinds
of a priori synthetical propositions above mentioned; only those which
are employed in philosophy can; according to the general mode of
speech; bear this n