the critique of pure reason-第116章
按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!
this case be destroyed by a practical addition; indeed; Reason would
be compelled to condemn herself; if she refused to comply with the
demands of the judgement; no superior to which we know… however
defective her understanding of the grounds of these demands might be。
This argument; although in fact transcendental; inasmuch as it rests
upon the intrinsic insufficiency of the contingent; is so simple and
natural; that the commonest understanding can appreciate its value。 We
see things around us change; arise; and pass away; they; or their
condition; must therefore have a cause。 The same demand must again
be made of the cause itself… as a datum of experience。 Now it is
natural that we should place the highest causality just where we place
supreme causality; in that being; which contains the conditions of all
possible effects; and the conception of which is so simple as that
of an all…embracing reality。 This highest cause; then; we regard as
absolutely necessary; because we find it absolutely necessary to
rise to it; and do not discover any reason for proceeding beyond it。
Thus; among all nations; through the darkest polytheism glimmer some
faint sparks of monotheism; to which these idolaters have been led;
not from reflection and profound thought; but by the study and natural
progress of the common understanding。
There are only three modes of proving the existence of a Deity; on
the grounds of speculative reason。
All the paths conducting to this end begin either from determinate
experience and the peculiar constitution of the world of sense; and
rise; according to the laws of causality; from it to the highest cause
existing apart from the world… or from a purely indeterminate
experience; that is; some empirical existence… or abstraction is
made of all experience; and the existence of a supreme cause is
concluded from a priori conceptions alone。 The first is the
physicotheological argument; the second the cosmological; the third
the ontological。 More there are not; and more there cannot be。
I shall show it is as unsuccessful on the one path… the empirical…
as on the other… the transcendental… and that it stretches its wings
in vain; to soar beyond the world of sense by the mere might of
speculative thought。 As regards the order in which we must discuss
those arguments; it will be exactly the reverse of that in which
reason; in the progress of its development; attains to them… the order
in which they are placed above。 For it will be made manifest to the
reader that; although experience presents the occasion and the
starting…point; it is the transcendental idea of reason which guides
it in its pilgrimage and is the goal of all its struggles。 I shall
therefore begin with an examination of the transcendental argument;
and afterwards inquire what additional strength has accrued to this
mode of proof from the addition of the empirical element。
SECTION IV。 Of the Impossibility of an Ontological Proof of
the Existence of God。
It is evident from what has been said that the conception of an
absolutely necessary being is a mere idea; the objective reality of
which is far from being established by the mere fact that it is a need
of reason。 On the contrary; this idea serves merely to indicate a
certain unattainable perfection; and rather limits the operations
than; by the presentation of new objects; extends the sphere of the
understanding。 But a strange anomaly meets us at the very threshold;
for the inference from a given existence in general to an absolutely
necessary existence seems to be correct and unavoidable; while the
conditions of the understanding refuse to aid us in forming any
conception of such a being。
Philosophers have always talked of an absolutely necessary being;
and have nevertheless declined to take the trouble of conceiving
whether… and how… a being of this nature is even cogitable; not to
mention that its existence is actually demonstrable。 A verbal
definition of the conception is certainly easy enough: it is something
the non…existence of which is impossible。 But does this definition
throw any light upon the conditions which render it impossible to
cogitate the non…existence of a thing… conditions which we wish to
ascertain; that we may discover whether we think anything in the
conception of such a being or not? For the mere fact that I throw
away; by means of the word unconditioned; all the conditions which the
understanding habitually requires in order to regard anything as
necessary; is very far from making clear whether by means of the
conception of the unconditionally necessary I think of something; or
really of nothing at all。
Nay; more; this chance…conception; now become so current; many
have endeavoured to explain by examples which seemed to render any
inquiries regarding its intelligibility quite needless。 Every
geometrical proposition… a triangle has three angles… it was said;
is absolutely necessary; and thus people talked of an object which lay
out of the sphere of our understanding as if it were perfectly plain
what the conception of such a being meant。
All the examples adduced have been drawn; without exception; from
judgements; and not from things。 But the unconditioned necessity of
a judgement does not form the absolute necessity of a thing。 On the
contrary; the absolute necessity of a judgement is only a
conditioned necessity of a thing; or of the predicate in a
judgement。 The proposition above…mentioned does not enounce that three
angles necessarily exist; but; upon condition that a triangle
exists; three angles must necessarily exist… in it。 And thus this
logical necessity has been the source of the greatest delusions。
Having formed an a priori conception of a thing; the content of
which was made to embrace existence; we believed ourselves safe in
concluding that; because existence belongs necessarily to the object
of the conception (that is; under the condition of my positing this
thing as given); the existence of the thing is also posited
necessarily; and that it is therefore absolutely necessary… merely
because its existence has been cogitated in the conception。
If; in an identical judgement; I annihilate the predicate in
thought; and retain the subject; a contradiction is the result; and
hence I say; the former belongs necessarily to the latter。 But if I
suppress both subject and predicate in thought; no contradiction
arises; for there is nothing at all; and therefore no means of forming
a contradiction。 To suppose the existence of a triangle and not that
of its three angles; is self…contradictory; but to suppose the
non…existence of both triangle and angles is perfectly admissible。 And
so is it with the conception of an absolutely necessary being。
Annihilate its existence in thought; and you annihilate the thing
itself with all its predicates; how then can there be any room for
contradiction? Externally; there is nothing to give rise to a
contradiction; for a thing cannot be necessary externally; nor
internally; for; by the annihilation or suppression of the thing
itself; its internal properties are also annihilated。 God is
omnipotent… that is a necessary judgement。 His omnipotence cannot be
denied; if the existence of a Deity is posited… the existence; that
is; of an infinite being; the two conceptions being identical。 But
when you say; God does not exist; neither omnipotence nor any other
predicate is affirmed; they must all disappear with the subject; and
in this judgement there cannot exist the least self…contradiction。
You have thus seen that when the predicate of a judgement is
annihilated in thought along with the subject; no internal
contradiction can arise; be the predicate what it may。 There is no
possibility of evading the conclusion… you find yourselves compelled
to declare: There are certain subjects which cannot be annihilated
in thought。 But this is nothing more than saying: There