introduction to the metaphysic of morals-第4章
按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!
nature; with the means of propagating; spreading; and strengthening
the moral principles… as by the education of the young and the
instruction of the people… and all other such doctrines and precepts
founded upon experience and indispensable in themselves; although they
must neither precede the metaphysical investigation of the
principles of reason; nor be mixed up with it。 For; by doing so; there
would be a great danger of laying down false; or at least very
flexible moral laws; which would hold forth as unattainable what is
not attached only because the law has not been comprehended and
presented in its purity; in which also its strength consists。 Or;
otherwise; spurious and mixed motives might be adopted instead of what
is dutiful and good in itself; and these would furnish no certain
moral principles either for the guidance of the judgement or for the
discipline of the heart in the practice of duty。 It is only by pure
reason; therefore; that duty can and must be prescribed。
The higher division of philosophy; under which the division just
mentioned stands; is into theoretical philosophy and practical
philosophy。 Practical philosophy is just moral philosophy in its
widest sense; as has been explained elsewhere。* All that is
practicable and possible; according to natural laws; is the special
subject of the activity of art; and its precepts and rules entirely
depend on the theory of nature。 It is only what is practicable
according to laws of freedom that can have principles independent of
theory; for there is no theory in relation to what passes beyond the
determinations of nature。 Philosophy therefore cannot embrace under
its practical division a technical theory; but only a morally
practical doctrine。 But if the dexterity of the will in acting
according to laws of freedom; in contradistinction to nature; were
to be also called an art; it would necessarily indicate an art which
would make a system of freedom possible like the system of nature。
This would truly be a Divine art; if we were in a position by means of
it to realize completely what reason prescribes to us; and to put
the idea into practice。
*In the Critique of Judgement (1790)。
III。 THE DIVISION OF A METAPHYSIC OF MORALS。
All legislation; whether relating to internal or external action;
and whether prescribed a priori by mere reason or laid down by the
will of another; involves two elements: First; a law which
represents the action that ought to happen as necessary objectively;
thus making the action a duty; second; a motive which connects the
principle determining the will to this action with the mental
representation of the law subjectively; so that the law makes duty the
motive of the action。 By the first element; the action is
represented as a duty; in accordance with the mere theoretical
knowledge of the possibility of determining the activity of the will
by practical rules。 By the second element; the obligation so to act is
connected in the subject with a determining principle of the will as
such。 All legislation; therefore; may be differentiated by reference
to its motive…principle。* The legislation which makes an action a
duty; and this duty at the same time a motive; is ethical。 That
legislation which does not include the motive…principle in the law;
and consequently admits another motive than the idea of duty itself;
is juridical。 In respect of the latter; it is evident that the motives
distinct from the idea of duty; to which it may refer; must be drawn
from the subjective (pathological) influences of inclination and of
aversion; determining the voluntary activity; and especially from
the latter; because it is a legislation which has to be compulsory;
and not merely a mode of attracting or persuading。 The agreement or
non…agreement of an action with the law; without reference to its
motive; is its legality; and that character of the action in which the
idea of duty arising from the law at the same time forms the motive of
the action; is its morality。
*This ground of division will apply; although the action which it
makes a duty may coincide with another action that may be otherwise
looked at from another point of view。 For instance; actions may in all
cases be classified as external。
Duties specially in accord with a juridical legislation can only
be external duties。 For this mode of legislation does not require that
the idea of the duty; which is internal; shall be of itself the
determining principle of the act of will; and as it requires a
motive suitable to the nature of its laws; it can only connect what is
external with the law。 Ethical legislation; on the other hand; makes
internal actions also duties; but not to the exclusion of the
external; for it embraces everything which is of the nature of duty。
And just because just because ethical legislation includes within
its law the internal motive of the action as contained in the idea
of duty; it involves a characteristic which cannot at all enter into
the legislation that is external。 Hence; ethical legislation cannot as
such be external; not even when proceeding from a Divine will;
although it may receive duties which rest on an external legislation
as duties; into the position of motives; within its own legislation。
From what has been said; it is evident that all duties; merely
because they are duties; belong to ethics; and yet the legislation
upon which they are founded is not on that account in all cases
contained in ethics。 On the contrary; the law of many of them lies
outside of ethics。 Thus ethics commands that I must fulfil a promise
entered into by contract; although the other party might not be able
to compel me to do so。 It adopts the law (pacta sunt servanda) and the
duty corresponding to it; from jurisprudence or the science of
right; by which they are established。 It is not in ethics;
therefore; but in jurisprudence; that the principle of the legislation
lies; that 〃promises made and accepted must be kept。〃 Accordingly;
ethics specially teaches that if the motive…principle of external
compulsion which juridical legislation connects with a duty is even
let go; the idea of duty alone is sufficient of itself as a motive。
For were it not so; and were the legislation itself not juridical; and
consequently the duty arising from it not specially a duty of right as
distinguished from a duty of virtue; then fidelity in the
performance of acts; to which the individual may be bound by the terms
of a contract; would have to be classified with acts of benevolence
and the obligation that underlies them; which cannot be correct。 To
keep one's promise is not properly a duty of virtue; but a duty of
right; and the performance of it can be enforced by external
compulsion。 But to keep one's promise; even when no compulsion can
be applied to enforce it; is; at the same time; a virtuous action; and
a proof of virtue。 jurisprudence as the science of right; and ethics
as the science of virtue; are therefore distinguished not so much by
their different duties; as rather by the difference Of the legislation
which connects the one or the other kind of motive with their laws。
Ethical legislation is that which cannot be external; although the
duties it prescribes may be external as well as internal。 Juridical
legislation is that which may also be external。 Thus it is an external
duty to keep a promise entered into by contract; but the injunction to
do this merely because it is a duty; without regard to any other
motive; belongs exclusively to the internal legislation。 It does not
belong thus to the ethical sphere as being a particular kind of duty
or a particular mode of action to which we are bound… for it is an
external duty in ethics as well as in jurisprudence… but it is because
the legislation in the case referred to is internal; and cannot have
an external lawgiver; that the obligation is reckoned as belonging
to e