the ethics(part ii)-第14章
按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!
To the first objection I answer; that I admit that the will has a
wider scope than the understanding; if by the understanding be
meant only clear and distinct ideas; but I deny that the will
has a wider scope than the perceptions; and the faculty of
forming conceptions; nor do I see why the faculty of volition
should be called infinite; any more than the faculty of feeling:
for; as we are able by the same faculty of volition to affirm an
infinite number of things (one after the other; for we cannot
affirm an infinite number simultaneously); so also can we; by
the same faculty of feeling; feel or perceive (in succession) an
infinite number of bodies。 If it be said that there is an
infinite number of things which we cannot perceive; I answer;
that we cannot attain to such things by any thinking; nor;
consequently; by any faculty of volition。 But; it may still be
urged; if God wished to bring it about that we should perceive
them; he would be obliged to endow us with a greater faculty of
perception; but not a greater faculty of volition than we have
already。 This is the same as to say that; if God wished to bring
it about that we should understand an infinite number of other
entities; it would be necessary for him to give us a greater
understanding; but not a more universal idea of entity than that
which we have already; in order to grasp such infinite entities。
We have shown that will is a universal entity or idea; whereby
we explain all particular volitionsin other words; that which
is common to all such volitions。
As; then; our opponents maintain that this idea; common or
universal to all volitions; is a faculty; it is little to be
wondered at that they assert; that such a faculty extends itself
into the infinite; beyond the limits of the understanding: for
what is universal is predicated alike of one; of many; and of an
infinite number of individuals。
To the second objection I reply by denying; that we have a free
power of suspending our judgment: for; when we say that anyone
suspends his judgment; we merely mean that he sees; that he does
not perceive the matter in question adequately。 Suspension of
judgment is; therefore; strictly speaking; a perception; and not
free will。 In order to illustrate the point; let us suppose a
boy imagining a horse; and perceive nothing else。 Inasmuch as
this imagination involves the existence of the horse (II。 xvii。
Cor。); and the boy does not perceive anything which would
exclude the existence of the horse; he will necessarily regard
the horse as present: he will not be able to doubt of its
existence; although he be not certain thereof。 We have daily
experience of such a state of things in dreams; and I do not
suppose that there is anyone; who would maintain that; while he
is dreaming; he has the free power of suspending his judgment
concerning the things in his dream; and bringing it about that
he should not dream those things; which he dreams that he sees;
yet it happens; notwithstanding; that even in dreams we suspend
our judgment; namely; when we dream that we are dreaming。
Further; I grant that no one can be deceived; so far as actual
perception extendsthat is; I grant that the mind's
imaginations; regarded in themselves; do not involve error (II。
xvii。 note); but I deny; that a man does not; in the act of
perception; make any affirmation。 For what is the perception of
a winged horse; save affirming that a horse has wings? If the
mind could perceive nothing else but the winged horse; it would
regard the same as present to itself: it would have no reasons
for doubting its existence; nor any faculty of dissent; unless
the imagination of a winged horse be joined to an idea which
precludes the existence of the said horse; or unless the mind
perceives that the idea which it possess of a winged horse is
inadequate; in which case it will either necessarily deny the
existence of such a horse; or will necessarily be in doubt on
the subject。
I think that I have anticipated my answer to the third objection;
namely; that the will is something universal which is predicated
of all ideas; and that it only signifies that which is common to
all ideas; namely; an affirmation; whose adequate essence must;
therefore; in so far as it is thus conceived in the abstract; be
in every idea; and be; in this respect alone; the same in all;
not in so far as it is considered as constituting the idea's
essence: for; in this respect; particular affirmations differ
one from the other; as much as do ideas。 For instance; the
affirmation which involves the idea of a circle; differs from
that which involves the idea of a triangle; as much as the idea
of a circle differs from the idea of a triangle。
Further; I absolutely deny; that we are in need of an equal power
of thinking; to affirm that that which is true is true; and to
affirm that that which is false is true。 These two
affirmations; if we regard the mind; are in the same relation to
one another as being and not…being; for there is nothing
positive in ideas; which constitutes the actual reality of
falsehood (II。 xxxv。 note; and xlvii。 note)。
We must therefore conclude; that we are easily deceived; when we
confuse universals with singulars; and the entities of reason
and abstractions with realities。 As for the fourth objection; I
am quite ready to admit; that a man placed in the equilibrium
described (namely; as perceiving nothing but hunger and thirst;
a certain food and a certain drink; each equally distant from
him) would die of hunger and thirst。 If I am asked; whether such
an one should not rather be considered an ass than a man; I
answer; that I do not know; neither do I know how a man should
be considered; who hangs himself; or how we should consider
children; fools; madmen; &c。
It remains to point out the advantages of a knowledge of this
doctrine as bearing on conduct; and this may be easily gathered
from what has been said。 The doctrine is good;
1。 Inasmuch as it teaches us to act solely according to the
decree of God; and to be partakers in the Divine nature; and so
much the more; as we perform more perfect actions and more and
more understand God。 Such a doctrine not only completely
tranquilizes our spirit; but also shows us where our highest
happiness or blessedness is; namely; solely in the knowledge of
God; whereby we are led to act only as love and piety shall bid
us。 We may thus clearly understand; how far astray from a true
estimate of virtue are those who expect to be decorated by God
with high rewards for their virtue; and their best actions; as
for having endured the direst slavery; as if virtue and the
service of God were not in itself happiness and perfect freedom。
2。 Inasmuch as it teaches us; how we ought to conduct ourselves
with respect to the gifts of fortune; or matters which are not
in our power; and do not follow from our nature。 For it shows
us; that we should await and endure fortune's smiles or frowns
with an equal mind; seeing that all things follow from the
eternal decree of God by the same necessity; as it follows from
the essence of a triangle; that the three angles are equal to two
right angles。
3。 This doctrine raises social life; inasmuch as it teaches us to
hate no man; neither to despise; to deride; to envy; or to be
angry with