on sophistical refutations-第12章
按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!
as e。g。 that 'speaking of the silent' is in one sense possible but
in another not possible: also that in one sense 'one should do what
must needs be done'; but not in another: for 'what must needs be'
bears a number of senses。 If; however; the ambiguity escapes one;
one should correct it at the end by making an addition to the
question: 'Is speaking of the silent possible?' 'No; but to speak of
while he is silent is possible。' Also; in cases which contain the
ambiguity in their premisses; one should reply in like manner: 'Do
people…then not understand what they know? 〃Yes; but not those who
know it in the manner described': for it is not the same thing to
say that 'those who know cannot understand what they know'; and to say
that 'those who know something in this particular manner cannot do
so'。 In general; too; even though he draws his conclusion in a quite
unambiguous manner; one should contend that what he has negated is not
the fact which one has asserted but only its name; and that
therefore there is no refutation。
20
It is evident also how one should solve those refutations that
depend upon the division and combination of words: for if the
expression means something different when divided and when combined;
as soon as one's opponent draws his conclusion one should take the
expression in the contrary way。 All such expressions as the
following depend upon the combination or division of the words: 'Was X
being beaten with that with which you saw him being beaten?' and
'Did you see him being beaten with that with which he was being
beaten?' This fallacy has also in it an element of amphiboly in the
questions; but it really depends upon combination。 For the meaning
that depends upon the division of the words is not really a double
meaning (for the expression when divided is not the same); unless also
the word that is pronounced; according to its breathing; as eros and
eros is a case of double meaning。 (In writing; indeed; a word is the
same whenever it is written of the same letters and in the same
manner… and even there people nowadays put marks at the side to
show the pronunciation… but the spoken words are not the same。)
Accordingly an expression that depends upon division is not an
ambiguous one。 It is evident also that not all refutations depend upon
ambiguity as some people say they do。
The answerer; then; must divide the expression: for
'I…saw…a…man…being…beaten with my eyes' is not the same as to say 'I
saw a man being…beaten…with…my…eyes'。 Also there is the argument of
Euthydemus proving 'Then you know now in Sicily that there are
triremes in Piraeus': and again; 'Can a good man who is a cobbler be
bad?' 'No。' 'But a good man may be a bad cobbler: therefore a good
cobbler will be bad。' Again; 'Things the knowledge of which is good;
are good things to learn; aren't they?' 'Yes。' 'The knowledge;
however; of evil is good: therefore evil is a good thing to know。'
'Yes。 But; you see; evil is both evil and a thing…to…learn; so that
evil is an evil…thing…to…learn; although the knowledge of evils is
good。' Again; 'Is it true to say in the present moment that you are
born?' 'Yes。' 'Then you are born in the present moment。' 'No; the
expression as divided has a different meaning: for it is true to
say…in…the…present…moment that 〃you are born〃; but not 〃You are
born…in…the…present…moment〃。' Again; 'Could you do what you can; and
as you can?' 'Yes。' 'But when not harping; you have the power to harp:
and therefore you could harp when not harping。' 'No: he has not the
power to harp…while…not…harping; merely; when he is not doing it; he
has the power to do it。' Some people solve this last refutation in
another way as well。 For; they say; if he has granted that he can do
anything in the way he can; still it does not follow that he can
harp when not harping: for it has not been granted that he will do
anything in every way in which he can; and it is not the same thing'
to do a thing in the way he can' and 'to do it in every way in which
he can'。 But evidently they do not solve it properly: for of arguments
that depend upon the same point the solution is the same; whereas this
will not fit all cases of the kind nor yet all ways of putting the
questions: it is valid against the questioner; but not against his
argument。
21
Accentuation gives rise to no fallacious arguments; either as
written or as spoken; except perhaps some few that might be made up;
e。g。 the following argument。 'Is ou katalueis a house?' 'Yes。' 'Is
then ou katalueis the negation of katalueis?' 'Yes。' 'But you
said that ou katalueis is a house: therefore the house is a
negation。' How one should solve this; is clear: for the word does
not mean the same when spoken with an acuter and when spoken with a
graver accent。
22
It is clear also how one must meet those fallacies that depend on
the identical expressions of things that are not identical; seeing
that we are in possession of the kinds of predications。 For the one
man; say; has granted; when asked; that a term denoting a substance
does not belong as an attribute; while the other has shown that some
attribute belongs which is in the Category of Relation or of Quantity;
but is usually thought to denote a substance because of its
expression; e。g。 in the following argument: 'Is it possible to be
doing and to have done the same thing at the same time?' 'No。' 'But;
you see; it is surely possible to be seeing and to have seen the
same thing at the same time; and in the same aspect。' Again; 'Is any
mode of passivity a mode of activity?' 'No。' 'Then 〃he is cut〃; 〃he is
burnt〃; 〃he is struck by some sensible object〃 are alike in expression
and all denote some form of passivity; while again 〃to say〃; 〃to run〃;
〃to see〃 are like one like one another in expression: but; you see;
〃to see〃 is surely a form of being struck by a sensible object;
therefore it is at the same time a form of passivity and of activity。'
Suppose; however; that in that case any one; after granting that it is
not possible to do and to have done the same thing in the same time;
were to say that it is possible to see and to have seen it; still he
has not yet been refuted; suppose him to say that 'to see' is not a
form of 'doing' (activity) but of 'passivity': for this question is
required as well; though he is supposed by the listener to have
already granted it; when he granted that 'to cut' is a form of
present; and 'to have cut' a form of past; activity; and so on with
the other things that have a like expression。 For the listener adds
the rest by himself; thinking the meaning to be alike: whereas
really the meaning is not alike; though it appears to be so because of
the expression。 The same thing happens here as happens in cases of
ambiguity: for in dealing with ambiguous expressions the tyro in
argument supposes the sophist to have negated the fact which he (the
tyro) affirmed; and not merely the name: whereas there still wants the
question whether in using the ambiguous term he had a single meaning
in view: for if he grants that that was so; the refutation will be
effected。
Like the above are also the following arguments。 It is asked if a
man has lost what he once had and afterwards has not: for a man will
no longer have ten dice even though he has only lost one die。 No:
rather it is that he has lost what he had before and has not now;
but there is no necessity for him to have lost as much or as many
things as he has not now。 So then; he asks the questions as to what he
has; and draws the conclusion as to the whole number that he has:
for