on sophistical refutations-第11章
按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!
then; one should not give a single answer to two questions; it is
evident that we should not say simply 'Yes' or 'No' in the case of
ambiguous terms either: for the remark is simply a remark; not an
answer at all; although among disputants such remarks are loosely
deemed to be answers; because they do not see what the consequence is。
As we said; then; inasmuch as certain refutations are generally
taken for such; though not such really; in the same way also certain
solutions will be generally taken for solutions; though not really
such。 Now these; we say; must sometimes be advanced rather than the
true solutions in contentious reasonings and in the encounter with
ambiguity。 The proper answer in saying what one thinks is to say
'Granted'; for in that way the likelihood of being refuted on a side
issue is minimized。 If; on the other hand; one is compelled to say
something paradoxical; one should then be most careful to add that 'it
seems' so: for in that way one avoids the impression of being either
refuted or paradoxical。 Since it is clear what is meant by 'begging
the original question'; and people think that they must at all costs
overthrow the premisses that lie near the conclusion; and plead in
excuse for refusing to grant him some of them that he is begging the
original question; so whenever any one claims from us a point such
as is bound to follow as a consequence from our thesis; but is false
or paradoxical; we must plead the same: for the necessary consequences
are generally held to be a part of the thesis itself。 Moreover;
whenever the universal has been secured not under a definite name; but
by a comparison of instances; one should say that the questioner
assumes it not in the sense in which it was granted nor in which he
proposed it in the premiss: for this too is a point upon which a
refutation often depends。
If one is debarred from these defences one must pass to the argument
that the conclusion has not been properly shown; approaching it in the
light of the aforesaid distinction between the different kinds of
fallacy。
In the case; then; of names that are used literally one is bound
to answer either simply or by drawing a distinction: the tacit
understandings implied in our statements; e。g。 in answer to
questions that are not put clearly but elliptically…it is upon this
that the consequent refutation depends。 For example; 'Is what
belongs to Athenians the property of Athenians?' Yes。 'And so it is
likewise in other cases。 But observe; man belongs to the animal
kingdom; doesn't he?' Yes。 'Then man is the property of the animal
kingdom。' But this is a fallacy: for we say that man 'belongs to'
the animal kingdom because he is an animal; just as we say that
Lysander 'belongs to' the Spartans; because he is a Spartan。 It is
evident; then; that where the premiss put forward is not clear; one
must not grant it simply。
Whenever of two things it is generally thought that if the one is
true the other is true of necessity; whereas; if the other is true;
the first is not true of necessity; one should; if asked which of them
is true; grant the smaller one: for the larger the number of
premisses; the harder it is to draw a conclusion from them。 If; again;
the sophist tries to secure that has a contrary while B has not;
suppose what he says is true; you should say that each has a contrary;
only for the one there is no established name。
Since; again; in regard to some of the views they express; most
people would say that any one who did not admit them was telling a
falsehood; while they would not say this in regard to some; e。g。 to
any matters whereon opinion is divided (for most people have no
distinct view whether the soul of animals is destructible or
immortal); accordingly (1) it is uncertain in which of two senses
the premiss proposed is usually meant…whether as maxims are (for
people call by the name of 'maxims' both true opinions and general
assertions) or like the doctrine 'the diagonal of a square is
incommensurate with its side': and moreover (2) whenever opinions
are divided as to the truth; we then have subjects of which it is very
easy to change the terminology undetected。 For because of the
uncertainty in which of the two senses the premiss contains the truth;
one will not be thought to be playing any trick; while because of
the division of opinion; one will not be thought to be telling a
falsehood。 Change the terminology therefore; for the change will
make the position irrefutable。
Moreover; whenever one foresees any question coming; one should
put in one's objection and have one's say beforehand: for by doing
so one is likely to embarrass the questioner most effectually。
18
Inasmuch as a proper solution is an exposure of false reasoning;
showing on what kind of question the falsity depends; and whereas
'false reasoning' has a double meaning…for it is used either if a
false conclusion has been proved; or if there is only an apparent
proof and no real one…there must be both the kind of solution just
described;' and also the correction of a merely apparent proof; so
as to show upon which of the questions the appearance depends。 Thus it
comes about that one solves arguments that are properly reasoned by
demolishing them; whereas one solves merely apparent arguments by
drawing distinctions。 Again; inasmuch as of arguments that are
properly reasoned some have a true and others a false conclusion;
those that are false in respect of their conclusion it is possible
to solve in two ways; for it is possible both by demolishing one of
the premisses asked; and by showing that the conclusion is not the
real state of the case: those; on the other hand; that are false in
respect of the premisses can be solved only by a demolition of one
of them; for the conclusion is true。 So that those who wish to solve
an argument should in the first place look and see if it is properly
reasoned; or is unreasoned; and next; whether the conclusion be true
or false; in order that we may effect the solution either by drawing
some distinction or by demolishing something; and demolishing it
either in this way or in that; as was laid down before。 There is a
very great deal of difference between solving an argument when being
subjected to questions and when not: for to foresee traps is
difficult; whereas to see them at one's leisure is easier。
19
Of the refutations; then; that depend upon ambiguity and amphiboly
some contain some question with more than one meaning; while others
contain a conclusion bearing a number of senses: e。g。 in the proof
that 'speaking of the silent' is possible; the conclusion has a double
meaning; while in the proof that 'he who knows does not understand
what he knows' one of the questions contains an amphiboly。 Also the
double…edged saying is true in one context but not in another: it
means something that is and something that is not。
Whenever; then; the many senses lie in the conclusion no
refutation takes place unless the sophist secures as well the
contradiction of the conclusion he means to prove; e。g。 in the proof
that 'seeing of the blind' is possible: for without the
contradiction there was no refutation。 Whenever; on the other hand;
the many senses lie in the questions; there is no necessity to begin
by denying the double…edged premiss: for this was not the goal of
the argument but only its support。 At the start; then; one should
reply with regard to an ambiguity; whether of a term or of a phrase;
in this manner; that 'in one sense it is so; and in another not so';
as e。g。 that 'speaking of the silent' is in one sense possible but
in an