贝壳电子书 > 英文原著电子书 > prior analytics >

第7章

prior analytics-第7章

小说: prior analytics 字数: 每页4000字

按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!






opposites also; 'it is possible to belong'; 'it is not impossible to



belong'; and 'it is not necessary not to belong'; will either be



identical or follow from one another。 For of everything the



affirmation or the denial holds good。 That which is possible then will



be not necessary and that which is not necessary will be possible。



It results that all premisses in the mode of possibility are



convertible into one another。 I mean not that the affirmative are



convertible into the negative; but that those which are affirmative in



form admit of conversion by opposition; e。g。 'it is possible to



belong' may be converted into 'it is possible not to belong'; and



'it is possible for A to belong to all B' into 'it is possible for A



to belong to no B' or 'not to all B'; and 'it is possible for A to



belong to some B' into 'it is possible for A not to belong to some B'。



And similarly the other propositions in this mode can be converted。



For since that which is possible is not necessary; and that which is



not necessary may possibly not belong; it is clear that if it is



possible that A should belong to B; it is possible also that it should



not belong to B: and if it is possible that it should belong to all;



it is also possible that it should not belong to all。 The same holds



good in the case of particular affirmations: for the proof is



identical。 And such premisses are affirmative and not negative; for



'to be possible' is in the same rank as 'to be'; as was said above。



  Having made these distinctions we next point out that the expression



'to be possible' is used in two ways。 In one it means to happen



generally and fall short of necessity; e。g。 man's turning grey or



growing or decaying; or generally what naturally belongs to a thing



(for this has not its necessity unbroken; since man's existence is not



continuous for ever; although if a man does exist; it comes about



either necessarily or generally)。 In another sense the expression



means the indefinite; which can be both thus and not thus; e。g。 an



animal's walking or an earthquake's taking place while it is



walking; or generally what happens by chance: for none of these



inclines by nature in the one way more than in the opposite。



  That which is possible in each of its two senses is convertible into



its opposite; not however in the same way: but what is natural is



convertible because it does not necessarily belong (for in this



sense it is possible that a man should not grow grey) and what is



indefinite is convertible because it inclines this way no more than



that。 Science and demonstrative syllogism are not concerned with



things which are indefinite; because the middle term is uncertain; but



they are concerned with things that are natural; and as a rule



arguments and inquiries are made about things which are possible in



this sense。 Syllogisms indeed can be made about the former; but it



is unusual at any rate to inquire about them。



  These matters will be treated more definitely in the sequel; our



business at present is to state the moods and nature of the



syllogism made from possible premisses。 The expression 'it is possible



for this to belong to that' may be understood in two senses: 'that'



may mean either that to which 'that' belongs or that to which it may



belong; for the expression 'A is possible of the subject of B' means



that it is possible either of that of which B is stated or of that



of which B may possibly be stated。 It makes no difference whether we



say; A is possible of the subject of B; or all B admits of A。 It is



clear then that the expression 'A may possibly belong to all B'



might be used in two senses。 First then we must state the nature and



characteristics of the syllogism which arises if B is possible of



the subject of C; and A is possible of the subject of B。 For thus both



premisses are assumed in the mode of possibility; but whenever A is



possible of that of which B is true; one premiss is a simple



assertion; the other a problematic。 Consequently we must start from



premisses which are similar in form; as in the other cases。







                                14







  Whenever A may possibly belong to all B; and B to all C; there



will be a perfect syllogism to prove that A may possibly belong to all



C。 This is clear from the definition: for it was in this way that we



explained 'to be possible for one term to belong to all of another'。



Similarly if it is possible for A to belong no B; and for B to



belong to all C; then it is possible for A to belong to no C。 For



the statement that it is possible for A not to belong to that of which



B may be true means (as we saw) that none of those things which can



possibly fall under the term B is left out of account。 But whenever



A may belong to all B; and B may belong to no C; then indeed no



syllogism results from the premisses assumed; but if the premiss BC is



converted after the manner of problematic propositions; the same



syllogism results as before。 For since it is possible that B should



belong to no C; it is possible also that it should belong to all C。



This has been stated above。 Consequently if B is possible for all C;



and A is possible for all B; the same syllogism again results。



Similarly if in both the premisses the negative is joined with 'it



is possible': e。g。 if A may belong to none of the Bs; and B to none of



the Cs。 No syllogism results from the assumed premisses; but if they



are converted we shall have the same syllogism as before。 It is



clear then that if the minor premiss is negative; or if both premisses



are negative; either no syllogism results; or if one it is not



perfect。 For the necessity results from the conversion。



  But if one of the premisses is universal; the other particular; when



the major premiss is universal there will be a perfect syllogism。



For if A is possible for all B; and B for some C; then A is possible



for some C。 This is clear from the definition of being possible。 Again



if A may belong to no B; and B may belong to some of the Cs; it is



necessary that A may possibly not belong to some of the Cs。 The



proof is the same as above。 But if the particular premiss is negative;



and the universal is affirmative; the major still being universal



and the minor particular; e。g。 A is possible for all B; B may possibly



not belong to some C; then a clear syllogism does not result from



the assumed premisses; but if the particular premiss is converted



and it is laid down that B possibly may belong to some C; we shall



have the same conclusion as before; as in the cases given at the



beginning。



  But if the major premiss is the minor universal; whether both are



affirmative; or negative; or different in quality; or if both are



indefinite or particular; in no way will a syllogism be possible。



For nothing prevents B from reaching beyond A; so that as predicates



cover unequal areas。 Let C be that by which B extends beyond A。 To C



it is not possible that A should belong…either to all or to none or to



some or not to some; since premisses in the mode of possibility are



convertible and it is possible for B to belong to more things than A



can。 Further; this is obvious if we take terms; for if the premisses



are as assumed; the major term is both possible for none of the



minor and must belong to all of it。 Take as terms common to all the



cases under consideration 'animal'…'white'…'man'; where the major



belongs necessarily to the minor; 'animal'…'white'…'garment'; where it



is not possible that the major should belong to the minor。 It is clear



then tha

返回目录 上一页 下一页 回到顶部 0 0

你可能喜欢的