prior analytics-第7章
按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!
opposites also; 'it is possible to belong'; 'it is not impossible to
belong'; and 'it is not necessary not to belong'; will either be
identical or follow from one another。 For of everything the
affirmation or the denial holds good。 That which is possible then will
be not necessary and that which is not necessary will be possible。
It results that all premisses in the mode of possibility are
convertible into one another。 I mean not that the affirmative are
convertible into the negative; but that those which are affirmative in
form admit of conversion by opposition; e。g。 'it is possible to
belong' may be converted into 'it is possible not to belong'; and
'it is possible for A to belong to all B' into 'it is possible for A
to belong to no B' or 'not to all B'; and 'it is possible for A to
belong to some B' into 'it is possible for A not to belong to some B'。
And similarly the other propositions in this mode can be converted。
For since that which is possible is not necessary; and that which is
not necessary may possibly not belong; it is clear that if it is
possible that A should belong to B; it is possible also that it should
not belong to B: and if it is possible that it should belong to all;
it is also possible that it should not belong to all。 The same holds
good in the case of particular affirmations: for the proof is
identical。 And such premisses are affirmative and not negative; for
'to be possible' is in the same rank as 'to be'; as was said above。
Having made these distinctions we next point out that the expression
'to be possible' is used in two ways。 In one it means to happen
generally and fall short of necessity; e。g。 man's turning grey or
growing or decaying; or generally what naturally belongs to a thing
(for this has not its necessity unbroken; since man's existence is not
continuous for ever; although if a man does exist; it comes about
either necessarily or generally)。 In another sense the expression
means the indefinite; which can be both thus and not thus; e。g。 an
animal's walking or an earthquake's taking place while it is
walking; or generally what happens by chance: for none of these
inclines by nature in the one way more than in the opposite。
That which is possible in each of its two senses is convertible into
its opposite; not however in the same way: but what is natural is
convertible because it does not necessarily belong (for in this
sense it is possible that a man should not grow grey) and what is
indefinite is convertible because it inclines this way no more than
that。 Science and demonstrative syllogism are not concerned with
things which are indefinite; because the middle term is uncertain; but
they are concerned with things that are natural; and as a rule
arguments and inquiries are made about things which are possible in
this sense。 Syllogisms indeed can be made about the former; but it
is unusual at any rate to inquire about them。
These matters will be treated more definitely in the sequel; our
business at present is to state the moods and nature of the
syllogism made from possible premisses。 The expression 'it is possible
for this to belong to that' may be understood in two senses: 'that'
may mean either that to which 'that' belongs or that to which it may
belong; for the expression 'A is possible of the subject of B' means
that it is possible either of that of which B is stated or of that
of which B may possibly be stated。 It makes no difference whether we
say; A is possible of the subject of B; or all B admits of A。 It is
clear then that the expression 'A may possibly belong to all B'
might be used in two senses。 First then we must state the nature and
characteristics of the syllogism which arises if B is possible of
the subject of C; and A is possible of the subject of B。 For thus both
premisses are assumed in the mode of possibility; but whenever A is
possible of that of which B is true; one premiss is a simple
assertion; the other a problematic。 Consequently we must start from
premisses which are similar in form; as in the other cases。
14
Whenever A may possibly belong to all B; and B to all C; there
will be a perfect syllogism to prove that A may possibly belong to all
C。 This is clear from the definition: for it was in this way that we
explained 'to be possible for one term to belong to all of another'。
Similarly if it is possible for A to belong no B; and for B to
belong to all C; then it is possible for A to belong to no C。 For
the statement that it is possible for A not to belong to that of which
B may be true means (as we saw) that none of those things which can
possibly fall under the term B is left out of account。 But whenever
A may belong to all B; and B may belong to no C; then indeed no
syllogism results from the premisses assumed; but if the premiss BC is
converted after the manner of problematic propositions; the same
syllogism results as before。 For since it is possible that B should
belong to no C; it is possible also that it should belong to all C。
This has been stated above。 Consequently if B is possible for all C;
and A is possible for all B; the same syllogism again results。
Similarly if in both the premisses the negative is joined with 'it
is possible': e。g。 if A may belong to none of the Bs; and B to none of
the Cs。 No syllogism results from the assumed premisses; but if they
are converted we shall have the same syllogism as before。 It is
clear then that if the minor premiss is negative; or if both premisses
are negative; either no syllogism results; or if one it is not
perfect。 For the necessity results from the conversion。
But if one of the premisses is universal; the other particular; when
the major premiss is universal there will be a perfect syllogism。
For if A is possible for all B; and B for some C; then A is possible
for some C。 This is clear from the definition of being possible。 Again
if A may belong to no B; and B may belong to some of the Cs; it is
necessary that A may possibly not belong to some of the Cs。 The
proof is the same as above。 But if the particular premiss is negative;
and the universal is affirmative; the major still being universal
and the minor particular; e。g。 A is possible for all B; B may possibly
not belong to some C; then a clear syllogism does not result from
the assumed premisses; but if the particular premiss is converted
and it is laid down that B possibly may belong to some C; we shall
have the same conclusion as before; as in the cases given at the
beginning。
But if the major premiss is the minor universal; whether both are
affirmative; or negative; or different in quality; or if both are
indefinite or particular; in no way will a syllogism be possible。
For nothing prevents B from reaching beyond A; so that as predicates
cover unequal areas。 Let C be that by which B extends beyond A。 To C
it is not possible that A should belong…either to all or to none or to
some or not to some; since premisses in the mode of possibility are
convertible and it is possible for B to belong to more things than A
can。 Further; this is obvious if we take terms; for if the premisses
are as assumed; the major term is both possible for none of the
minor and must belong to all of it。 Take as terms common to all the
cases under consideration 'animal'…'white'…'man'; where the major
belongs necessarily to the minor; 'animal'…'white'…'garment'; where it
is not possible that the major should belong to the minor。 It is clear
then tha