贝壳电子书 > 英文原著电子书 > prior analytics >

第33章

prior analytics-第33章

小说: prior analytics 字数: 每页4000字

按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!






secondly if instead of inviting assent to propositions which are



closely connected they take as far as possible those that are not



connected by middle terms。 For example suppose that A is to be



inferred to be true of F; B; C; D; and E being middle terms。 One ought



then to ask whether A belongs to B; and next whether D belongs to E;



instead of asking whether B belongs to C; after that he may ask



whether B belongs to C; and so on。 If the syllogism is drawn through



one middle term; he ought to begin with that: in this way he will most



likely deceive his opponent。







                                20







  Since we know when a syllogism can be formed and how its terms



must be related; it is clear when refutation will be possible and when



impossible。 A refutation is possible whether everything is conceded;



or the answers alternate (one; I mean; being affirmative; the other



negative)。 For as has been shown a syllogism is possible whether the



terms are related in affirmative propositions or one proposition is



affirmative; the other negative: consequently; if what is laid down is



contrary to the conclusion; a refutation must take place: for a



refutation is a syllogism which establishes the contradictory。 But



if nothing is conceded; a refutation is impossible: for no syllogism



is possible (as we saw) when all the terms are negative: therefore



no refutation is possible。 For if a refutation were possible; a



syllogism must be possible; although if a syllogism is possible it



does not follow that a refutation is possible。 Similarly refutation is



not possible if nothing is conceded universally: since the fields of



refutation and syllogism are defined in the same way。







                                21







  It sometimes happens that just as we are deceived in the arrangement



of the terms; so error may arise in our thought about them; e。g。 if it



is possible that the same predicate should belong to more than one



subject immediately; but although knowing the one; a man may forget



the other and think the opposite true。 Suppose that A belongs to B and



to C in virtue of their nature; and that B and C belong to all D in



the same way。 If then a man thinks that A belongs to all B; and B to



D; but A to no C; and C to all D; he will both know and not know the



same thing in respect of the same thing。 Again if a man were to make a



mistake about the members of a single series; e。g。 suppose A belongs



to B; B to C; and C to D; but some one thinks that A belongs to all B;



but to no C: he will both know that A belongs to D; and think that



it does not。 Does he then maintain after this simply that what he



knows; he does not think? For he knows in a way that A belongs to C



through B; since the part is included in the whole; so that what he



knows in a way; this he maintains he does not think at all: but that



is impossible。



  In the former case; where the middle term does not belong to the



same series; it is not possible to think both the premisses with



reference to each of the two middle terms: e。g。 that A belongs to



all B; but to no C; and both B and C belong to all D。 For it turns out



that the first premiss of the one syllogism is either wholly or



partially contrary to the first premiss of the other。 For if he thinks



that A belongs to everything to which B belongs; and he knows that B



belongs to D; then he knows that A belongs to D。 Consequently if again



he thinks that A belongs to nothing to which C belongs; he thinks that



A does not belong to some of that to which B belongs; but if he thinks



that A belongs to everything to which B belongs; and again thinks that



A does not belong to some of that to which B belongs; these beliefs



are wholly or partially contrary。 In this way then it is not



possible to think; but nothing prevents a man thinking one premiss



of each syllogism of both premisses of one of the two syllogisms: e。g。



A belongs to all B; and B to D; and again A belongs to no C。 An



error of this kind is similar to the error into which we fall



concerning particulars: e。g。 if A belongs to all B; and B to all C;



A will belong to all C。 If then a man knows that A belongs to



everything to which B belongs; he knows that A belongs to C。 But



nothing prevents his being ignorant that C exists; e。g。 let A stand



for two right angles; B for triangle; C for a particular diagram of



a triangle。 A man might think that C did not exist; though he knew



that every triangle contains two right angles; consequently he will



know and not know the same thing at the same time。 For the



expression 'to know that every triangle has its angles equal to two



right angles' is ambiguous; meaning to have the knowledge either of



the universal or of the particulars。 Thus then he knows that C



contains two right angles with a knowledge of the universal; but not



with a knowledge of the particulars; consequently his knowledge will



not be contrary to his ignorance。 The argument in the Meno that



learning is recollection may be criticized in a similar way。 For it



never happens that a man starts with a foreknowledge of the



particular; but along with the process of being led to see the general



principle he receives a knowledge of the particulars; by an act (as it



were) of recognition。 For we know some things directly; e。g。 that



the angles are equal to two right angles; if we know that the figure



is a triangle。 Similarly in all other cases。



  By a knowledge of the universal then we see the particulars; but



we do not know them by the kind of knowledge which is proper to



them; consequently it is possible that we may make mistakes about



them; but not that we should have the knowledge and error that are



contrary to one another: rather we have the knowledge of the universal



but make a mistake in apprehending the particular。 Similarly in the



cases stated above。 The error in respect of the middle term is not



contrary to the knowledge obtained through the syllogism; nor is the



thought in respect of one middle term contrary to that in respect of



the other。 Nothing prevents a man who knows both that A belongs to the



whole of B; and that B again belongs to C; thinking that A does not



belong to C; e。g。 knowing that every mule is sterile and that this



is a mule; and thinking that this animal is with foal: for he does not



know that A belongs to C; unless he considers the two propositions



together。 So it is evident that if he knows the one and does not



know the other; he will fall into error。 And this is the relation of



knowledge of the universal to knowledge of the particular。 For we know



no sensible thing; once it has passed beyond the range of our



senses; even if we happen to have perceived it; except by means of the



universal and the possession of the knowledge which is proper to the



particular; but without the actual exercise of that knowledge。 For



to know is used in three senses: it may mean either to have



knowledge of the universal or to have knowledge proper to the matter



in hand or to exercise such knowledge: consequently three kinds of



error also are possible。 Nothing then prevents a man both knowing



and being mistaken about the same thing; provided that his knowledge



and his error are not contrary。 And this happens also to the man whose



knowledge is limited to each of the premisses and who has not



previously considered the particular question。 For when he thinks that



the mule is with foal he has not the knowledge in the sense of its



actual exercise; nor on the other hand has his thought caused an error



contrary t

返回目录 上一页 下一页 回到顶部 0 0

你可能喜欢的