贝壳电子书 > 英文原著电子书 > prior analytics >

第32章

prior analytics-第32章

小说: prior analytics 字数: 每页4000字

按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!






described and effecting a reciprocal proof with three propositions。



  Similarly if he should assume that B belongs to C; this being as



uncertain as the question whether A belongs to C; the question is



not yet begged; but no demonstration is made。 If however A and B are



identical either because they are convertible or because A follows



B; then the question is begged for the same reason as before。 For we



have explained the meaning of begging the question; viz。 proving



that which is not self…evident by means of itself。



  If then begging the question is proving what is not self…evident



by means of itself; in other words failing to prove when the failure



is due to the thesis to be proved and the premiss through which it



is proved being equally uncertain; either because predicates which are



identical belong to the same subject; or because the same predicate



belongs to subjects which are identical; the question may be begged in



the middle and third figures in both ways; though; if the syllogism is



affirmative; only in the third and first figures。 If the syllogism



is negative; the question is begged when identical predicates are



denied of the same subject; and both premisses do not beg the question



indifferently (in a similar way the question may be begged in the



middle figure); because the terms in negative syllogisms are not



convertible。 In scientific demonstrations the question is begged



when the terms are really related in the manner described; in



dialectical arguments when they are according to common opinion so



related。







                                17







  The objection that 'this is not the reason why the result is false';



which we frequently make in argument; is made primarily in the case of



a reductio ad impossibile; to rebut the proposition which was being



proved by the reduction。 For unless a man has contradicted this



proposition he will not say; 'False cause'; but urge that something



false has been assumed in the earlier parts of the argument; nor



will he use the formula in the case of an ostensive proof; for here



what one denies is not assumed as a premiss。 Further when anything



is refuted ostensively by the terms ABC; it cannot be objected that



the syllogism does not depend on the assumption laid down。 For we



use the expression 'false cause'; when the syllogism is concluded in



spite of the refutation of this position; but that is not possible



in ostensive proofs: since if an assumption is refuted; a syllogism



can no longer be drawn in reference to it。 It is clear then that the



expression 'false cause' can only be used in the case of a reductio ad



impossibile; and when the original hypothesis is so related to the



impossible conclusion; that the conclusion results indifferently



whether the hypothesis is made or not。 The most obvious case of the



irrelevance of an assumption to a conclusion which is false is when



a syllogism drawn from middle terms to an impossible conclusion is



independent of the hypothesis; as we have explained in the Topics。 For



to put that which is not the cause as the cause; is just this: e。g。 if



a man; wishing to prove that the diagonal of the square is



incommensurate with the side; should try to prove Zeno's theorem



that motion is impossible; and so establish a reductio ad impossibile:



for Zeno's false theorem has no connexion at all with the original



assumption。 Another case is where the impossible conclusion is



connected with the hypothesis; but does not result from it。 This may



happen whether one traces the connexion upwards or downwards; e。g。



if it is laid down that A belongs to B; B to C; and C to D; and it



should be false that B belongs to D: for if we eliminated A and



assumed all the same that B belongs to C and C to D; the false



conclusion would not depend on the original hypothesis。 Or again trace



the connexion upwards; e。g。 suppose that A belongs to B; E to A and



F to E; it being false that F belongs to A。 In this way too the



impossible conclusion would result; though the original hypothesis



were eliminated。 But the impossible conclusion ought to be connected



with the original terms: in this way it will depend on the hypothesis;



e。g。 when one traces the connexion downwards; the impossible



conclusion must be connected with that term which is predicate in



the hypothesis: for if it is impossible that A should belong to D; the



false conclusion will no longer result after A has been eliminated。 If



one traces the connexion upwards; the impossible conclusion must be



connected with that term which is subject in the hypothesis: for if it



is impossible that F should belong to B; the impossible conclusion



will disappear if B is eliminated。 Similarly when the syllogisms are



negative。



  It is clear then that when the impossibility is not related to the



original terms; the false conclusion does not result on account of the



assumption。 Or perhaps even so it may sometimes be independent。 For if



it were laid down that A belongs not to B but to K; and that K belongs



to C and C to D; the impossible conclusion would still stand。



Similarly if one takes the terms in an ascending series。



Consequently since the impossibility results whether the first



assumption is suppressed or not; it would appear to be independent



of that assumption。 Or perhaps we ought not to understand the



statement that the false conclusion results independently of the



assumption; in the sense that if something else were supposed the



impossibility would result; but rather we mean that when the first



assumption is eliminated; the same impossibility results through the



remaining premisses; since it is not perhaps absurd that the same



false result should follow from several hypotheses; e。g。 that



parallels meet; both on the assumption that the interior angle is



greater than the exterior and on the assumption that a triangle



contains more than two right angles。







                                18







  A false argument depends on the first false statement in it。 Every



syllogism is made out of two or more premisses。 If then the false



conclusion is drawn from two premisses; one or both of them must be



false: for (as we proved) a false syllogism cannot be drawn from two



premisses。 But if the premisses are more than two; e。g。 if C is



established through A and B; and these through D; E; F; and G; one



of these higher propositions must be false; and on this the argument



depends: for A and B are inferred by means of D; E; F; and G。



Therefore the conclusion and the error results from one of them。







                                19







  In order to avoid having a syllogism drawn against us we must take



care; whenever an opponent asks us to admit the reason without the



conclusions; not to grant him the same term twice over in his



premisses; since we know that a syllogism cannot be drawn without a



middle term; and that term which is stated more than once is the



middle。 How we ought to watch the middle in reference to each



conclusion; is evident from our knowing what kind of thesis is



proved in each figure。 This will not escape us since we know how we



are maintaining the argument。



  That which we urge men to beware of in their admissions; they



ought in attack to try to conceal。 This will be possible first; if;



instead of drawing the conclusions of preliminary syllogisms; they



take the necessary premisses and leave the conclusions in the dark;



secondly if instead of inviting assent to propositions which are



closely connected they take 

返回目录 上一页 下一页 回到顶部 0 0

你可能喜欢的