贝壳电子书 > 英文原著电子书 > prior analytics >

第27章

prior analytics-第27章

小说: prior analytics 字数: 每页4000字

按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!






belong to all B; and to no C: we conclude that B belongs to no C。 If



then it is assumed that B belongs to all A; it is necessary that A



should belong to no C: for we get the second figure; with B as middle。



But if the premiss AB was negative; and the other affirmative; we



shall have the first figure。 For C belongs to all A and B to no C;



consequently B belongs to no A: neither then does A belong to B。



Through the conclusion; therefore; and one premiss; we get no



syllogism; but if another premiss is assumed in addition; a



syllogism will be possible。 But if the syllogism not universal; the



universal premiss cannot be proved; for the same reason as we gave



above; but the particular premiss can be proved whenever the universal



statement is affirmative。 Let A belong to all B; and not to all C: the



conclusion is BC。 If then it is assumed that B belongs to all A; but



not to all C; A will not belong to some C; B being middle。 But if



the universal premiss is negative; the premiss AC will not be



demonstrated by the conversion of AB: for it turns out that either



both or one of the premisses is negative; consequently a syllogism



will not be possible。 But the proof will proceed as in the universal



syllogisms; if it is assumed that A belongs to some of that to some of



which B does not belong。







                                 7







  In the third figure; when both premisses are taken universally; it



is not possible to prove them reciprocally: for that which is



universal is proved through statements which are universal; but the



conclusion in this figure is always particular; so that it is clear



that it is not possible at all to prove through this figure the



universal premiss。 But if one premiss is universal; the other



particular; proof of the latter will sometimes be possible;



sometimes not。 When both the premisses assumed are affirmative; and



the universal concerns the minor extreme; proof will be possible;



but when it concerns the other extreme; impossible。 Let A belong to



all C and B to some C: the conclusion is the statement AB。 If then



it is assumed that C belongs to all A; it has been proved that C



belongs to some B; but that B belongs to some C has not been proved。



And yet it is necessary; if C belongs to some B; that B should



belong to some C。 But it is not the same that this should belong to



that; and that to this: but we must assume besides that if this



belongs to some of that; that belongs to some of this。 But if this



is assumed the syllogism no longer results from the conclusion and the



other premiss。 But if B belongs to all C; and A to some C; it will



be possible to prove the proposition AC; when it is assumed that C



belongs to all B; and A to some B。 For if C belongs to all B and A



to some B; it is necessary that A should belong to some C; B being



middle。 And whenever one premiss is affirmative the other negative;



and the affirmative is universal; the other premiss can be proved。 Let



B belong to all C; and A not to some C: the conclusion is that A



does not belong to some B。 If then it is assumed further that C



belongs to all B; it is necessary that A should not belong to some



C; B being middle。 But when the negative premiss is universal; the



other premiss is not except as before; viz。 if it is assumed that that



belongs to some of that; to some of which this does not belong; e。g。



if A belongs to no C; and B to some C: the conclusion is that A does



not belong to some B。 If then it is assumed that C belongs to some



of that to some of which does not belong; it is necessary that C



should belong to some of the Bs。 In no other way is it possible by



converting the universal premiss to prove the other: for in no other



way can a syllogism be formed。



  It is clear then that in the first figure reciprocal proof is made



both through the third and through the first figure…if the



conclusion is affirmative through the first; if the conclusion is



negative through the last。 For it is assumed that that belongs to



all of that to none of which this belongs。 In the middle figure;



when the syllogism is universal; proof is possible through the



second figure and through the first; but when particular through the



second and the last。 In the third figure all proofs are made through



itself。 It is clear also that in the third figure and in the middle



figure those syllogisms which are not made through those figures



themselves either are not of the nature of circular proof or are



imperfect。







                                 8







  To convert a syllogism means to alter the conclusion and make



another syllogism to prove that either the extreme cannot belong to



the middle or the middle to the last term。 For it is necessary; if the



conclusion has been changed into its opposite and one of the premisses



stands; that the other premiss should be destroyed。 For if it should



stand; the conclusion also must stand。 It makes a difference whether



the conclusion is converted into its contradictory or into its



contrary。 For the same syllogism does not result whichever form the



conversion takes。 This will be made clear by the sequel。 By



contradictory opposition I mean the opposition of 'to all' to 'not



to all'; and of 'to some' to 'to none'; by contrary opposition I



mean the opposition of 'to all' to 'to none'; and of 'to some' to 'not



to some'。 Suppose that A been proved of C; through B as middle term。



If then it should be assumed that A belongs to no C; but to all B; B



will belong to no C。 And if A belongs to no C; and B to all C; A



will belong; not to no B at all; but not to all B。 For (as we saw) the



universal is not proved through the last figure。 In a word it is not



possible to refute universally by conversion the premiss which



concerns the major extreme: for the refutation always proceeds through



the third since it is necessary to take both premisses in reference to



the minor extreme。 Similarly if the syllogism is negative。 Suppose



it has been proved that A belongs to no C through B。 Then if it is



assumed that A belongs to all C; and to no B; B will belong to none of



the Cs。 And if A and B belong to all C; A will belong to some B: but



in the original premiss it belonged to no B。



  If the conclusion is converted into its contradictory; the



syllogisms will be contradictory and not universal。 For one premiss is



particular; so that the conclusion also will be particular。 Let the



syllogism be affirmative; and let it be converted as stated。 Then if A



belongs not to all C; but to all B; B will belong not to all C。 And if



A belongs not to all C; but B belongs to all C; A will belong not to



all B。 Similarly if the syllogism is negative。 For if A belongs to



some C; and to no B; B will belong; not to no C at all; but…not to



some C。 And if A belongs to some C; and B to all C; as was



originally assumed; A will belong to some B。



  In particular syllogisms when the conclusion is converted into its



contradictory; both premisses may be refuted; but when it is converted



into its contrary; neither。 For the result is no longer; as in the



universal syllogisms; refutation in which the conclusion reached by O;



conversion lacks universality; but no refutation at all。 Suppose



that A has been proved of some C。 If then it is assumed that A belongs



to no C; and B to some C; A will not belong to some B: and if A



belongs to no C; but to all B; B will belong to no C。 Thus both



premisses are refuted。 But neither can be refuted if the conclusion is



converted into its contrary。 For if A does not be

返回目录 上一页 下一页 回到顶部 0 0

你可能喜欢的