贝壳电子书 > 英文原著电子书 > prior analytics >

第14章

prior analytics-第14章

小说: prior analytics 字数: 每页4000字

按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!






mean not only in being affirmative or negative; but also in being



necessary; pure; problematic。 We must consider also the other forms of



predication。



  It is clear also when a syllogism in general can be made and when it



cannot; and when a valid; when a perfect syllogism can be formed;



and that if a syllogism is formed the terms must be arranged in one of



the ways that have been mentioned。







                                25







  It is clear too that every demonstration will proceed through



three terms and no more; unless the same conclusion is established



by different pairs of propositions; e。g。 the conclusion E may be



established through the propositions A and B; and through the



propositions C and D; or through the propositions A and B; or A and C;



or B and C。 For nothing prevents there being several middles for the



same terms。 But in that case there is not one but several



syllogisms。 Or again when each of the propositions A and B is obtained



by syllogistic inference; e。g。 by means of D and E; and again B by



means of F and G。 Or one may be obtained by syllogistic; the other



by inductive inference。 But thus also the syllogisms are many; for the



conclusions are many; e。g。 A and B and C。 But if this can be called



one syllogism; not many; the same conclusion may be reached by more



than three terms in this way; but it cannot be reached as C is



established by means of A and B。 Suppose that the proposition E is



inferred from the premisses A; B; C; and D。 It is necessary then



that of these one should be related to another as whole to part: for



it has already been proved that if a syllogism is formed some of its



terms must be related in this way。 Suppose then that A stands in



this relation to B。 Some conclusion then follows from them。 It must



either be E or one or other of C and D; or something other than these。



  (1) If it is E the syllogism will have A and B for its sole



premisses。 But if C and D are so related that one is whole; the



other part; some conclusion will follow from them also; and it must be



either E; or one or other of the propositions A and B; or something



other than these。 And if it is (i) E; or (ii) A or B; either (i) the



syllogisms will be more than one; or (ii) the same thing happens to be



inferred by means of several terms only in the sense which we saw to



be possible。 But if (iii) the conclusion is other than E or A or B;



the syllogisms will be many; and unconnected with one another。 But



if C is not so related to D as to make a syllogism; the propositions



will have been assumed to no purpose; unless for the sake of induction



or of obscuring the argument or something of the sort。



  (2) But if from the propositions A and B there follows not E but



some other conclusion; and if from C and D either A or B follows or



something else; then there are several syllogisms; and they do not



establish the conclusion proposed: for we assumed that the syllogism



proved E。 And if no conclusion follows from C and D; it turns out that



these propositions have been assumed to no purpose; and the



syllogism does not prove the original proposition。



  So it is clear that every demonstration and every syllogism will



proceed through three terms only。



  This being evident; it is clear that a syllogistic conclusion



follows from two premisses and not from more than two。 For the three



terms make two premisses; unless a new premiss is assumed; as was said



at the beginning; to perfect the syllogisms。 It is clear therefore



that in whatever syllogistic argument the premisses through which



the main conclusion follows (for some of the preceding conclusions



must be premisses) are not even in number; this argument either has



not been drawn syllogistically or it has assumed more than was



necessary to establish its thesis。



  If then syllogisms are taken with respect to their main premisses;



every syllogism will consist of an even number of premisses and an odd



number of terms (for the terms exceed the premisses by one); and the



conclusions will be half the number of the premisses。 But whenever a



conclusion is reached by means of prosyllogisms or by means of several



continuous middle terms; e。g。 the proposition AB by means of the



middle terms C and D; the number of the terms will similarly exceed



that of the premisses by one (for the extra term must either be



added outside or inserted: but in either case it follows that the



relations of predication are one fewer than the terms related); and



the premisses will be equal in number to the relations of predication。



The premisses however will not always be even; the terms odd; but they



will alternate…when the premisses are even; the terms must be odd;



when the terms are even; the premisses must be odd: for along with one



term one premiss is added; if a term is added from any quarter。



Consequently since the premisses were (as we saw) even; and the



terms odd; we must make them alternately even and odd at each



addition。 But the conclusions will not follow the same arrangement



either in respect to the terms or to the premisses。 For if one term is



added; conclusions will be added less by one than the pre…existing



terms: for the conclusion is drawn not in relation to the single



term last added; but in relation to all the rest; e。g。 if to ABC the



term D is added; two conclusions are thereby added; one in relation to



A; the other in relation to B。 Similarly with any further additions。



And similarly too if the term is inserted in the middle: for in



relation to one term only; a syllogism will not be constructed。



Consequently the conclusions will be much more numerous than the terms



or the premisses。







                                26







  Since we understand the subjects with which syllogisms are



concerned; what sort of conclusion is established in each figure;



and in how many moods this is done; it is evident to us both what sort



of problem is difficult and what sort is easy to prove。 For that which



is concluded in many figures and through many moods is easier; that



which is concluded in few figures and through few moods is more



difficult to attempt。 The universal affirmative is proved by means



of the first figure only and by this in only one mood; the universal



negative is proved both through the first figure and through the



second; through the first in one mood; through the second in two。



The particular affirmative is proved through the first and through the



last figure; in one mood through the first; in three moods through the



last。 The particular negative is proved in all the figures; but once



in the first; in two moods in the second; in three moods in the third。



It is clear then that the universal affirmative is most difficult to



establish; most easy to overthrow。 In general; universals are easier



game for the destroyer than particulars: for whether the predicate



belongs to none or not to some; they are destroyed: and the particular



negative is proved in all the figures; the universal negative in



two。 Similarly with universal negatives: the original statement is



destroyed; whether the predicate belongs to all or to some: and this



we found possible in two figures。 But particular statements can be



refuted in one way only…by proving that the predicate belongs either



to all or to none。 But particular statements are easier to



establish: for proof is possible in more figures and through more



moods。 And in general we must not forget that it is possible to refute



statements by means of one another; I mean; universal s

返回目录 上一页 下一页 回到顶部 0 0

你可能喜欢的