prior analytics-第12章
按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!
premiss is necessary; if it is affirmative the conclusion will be
neither necessary or assertoric; but if it is negative the syllogism
will result in a negative assertoric proposition; as above。 In these
also we must understand the expression 'possible' in the conclusion in
the same way as before。
First let the premisses be problematic and suppose that both A and B
may possibly belong to every C。 Since then the affirmative proposition
is convertible into a particular; and B may possibly belong to every
C; it follows that C may possibly belong to some B。 So; if A is
possible for every C; and C is possible for some of the Bs; then A
is possible for some of the Bs。 For we have got the first figure。
And A if may possibly belong to no C; but B may possibly belong to all
C; it follows that A may possibly not belong to some B: for we shall
have the first figure again by conversion。 But if both premisses
should be negative no necessary consequence will follow from them as
they are stated; but if the premisses are converted into their
corresponding affirmatives there will be a syllogism as before。 For if
A and B may possibly not belong to C; if 'may possibly belong' is
substituted we shall again have the first figure by means of
conversion。 But if one of the premisses is universal; the other
particular; a syllogism will be possible; or not; under the
arrangement of the terms as in the case of assertoric propositions。
Suppose that A may possibly belong to all C; and B to some C。 We shall
have the first figure again if the particular premiss is converted。
For if A is possible for all C; and C for some of the Bs; then A is
possible for some of the Bs。 Similarly if the proposition BC is
universal。 Likewise also if the proposition AC is negative; and the
proposition BC affirmative: for we shall again have the first figure
by conversion。 But if both premisses should be negative…the one
universal and the other particular…although no syllogistic
conclusion will follow from the premisses as they are put; it will
follow if they are converted; as above。 But when both premisses are
indefinite or particular; no syllogism can be formed: for A must
belong sometimes to all B and sometimes to no B。 To illustrate the
affirmative relation take the terms animal…man…white; to illustrate
the negative; take the terms horse…man…whitewhite being the middle
term。
21
If one premiss is pure; the other problematic; the conclusion will
be problematic; not pure; and a syllogism will be possible under the
same arrangement of the terms as before。 First let the premisses be
affirmative: suppose that A belongs to all C; and B may possibly
belong to all C。 If the proposition BC is converted; we shall have the
first figure; and the conclusion that A may possibly belong to some of
the Bs。 For when one of the premisses in the first figure is
problematic; the conclusion also (as we saw) is problematic。 Similarly
if the proposition BC is pure; AC problematic; or if AC is negative;
BC affirmative; no matter which of the two is pure; in both cases
the conclusion will be problematic: for the first figure is obtained
once more; and it has been proved that if one premiss is problematic
in that figure the conclusion also will be problematic。 But if the
minor premiss BC is negative; or if both premisses are negative; no
syllogistic conclusion can be drawn from the premisses as they
stand; but if they are converted a syllogism is obtained as before。
If one of the premisses is universal; the other particular; then
when both are affirmative; or when the universal is negative; the
particular affirmative; we shall have the same sort of syllogisms: for
all are completed by means of the first figure。 So it is clear that we
shall have not a pure but a problematic syllogistic conclusion。 But if
the affirmative premiss is universal; the negative particular; the
proof will proceed by a reductio ad impossibile。 Suppose that B
belongs to all C; and A may possibly not belong to some C: it
follows that may possibly not belong to some B。 For if A necessarily
belongs to all B; and B (as has been assumed) belongs to all C; A will
necessarily belong to all C: for this has been proved before。 But it
was assumed at the outset that A may possibly not belong to some C。
Whenever both premisses are indefinite or particular; no syllogism
will be possible。 The demonstration is the same as was given in the
case of universal premisses; and proceeds by means of the same terms。
22
If one of the premisses is necessary; the other problematic; when
the premisses are affirmative a problematic affirmative conclusion can
always be drawn; when one proposition is affirmative; the other
negative; if the affirmative is necessary a problematic negative can
be inferred; but if the negative proposition is necessary both a
problematic and a pure negative conclusion are possible。 But a
necessary negative conclusion will not be possible; any more than in
the other figures。 Suppose first that the premisses are affirmative;
i。e。 that A necessarily belongs to all C; and B may possibly belong to
all C。 Since then A must belong to all C; and C may belong to some
B; it follows that A may (not does) belong to some B: for so it
resulted in the first figure。 A similar proof may be given if the
proposition BC is necessary; and AC is problematic。 Again suppose
one proposition is affirmative; the other negative; the affirmative
being necessary: i。e。 suppose A may possibly belong to no C; but B
necessarily belongs to all C。 We shall have the first figure once
more: and…since the negative premiss is problematic…it is clear that
the conclusion will be problematic: for when the premisses stand
thus in the first figure; the conclusion (as we found) is problematic。
But if the negative premiss is necessary; the conclusion will be not
only that A may possibly not belong to some B but also that it does
not belong to some B。 For suppose that A necessarily does not belong
to C; but B may belong to all C。 If the affirmative proposition BC
is converted; we shall have the first figure; and the negative premiss
is necessary。 But when the premisses stood thus; it resulted that A
might possibly not belong to some C; and that it did not belong to
some C; consequently here it follows that A does not belong to some B。
But when the minor premiss is negative; if it is problematic we
shall have a syllogism by altering the premiss into its
complementary affirmative; as before; but if it is necessary no
syllogism can be formed。 For A sometimes necessarily belongs to all B;
and sometimes cannot possibly belong to any B。 To illustrate the
former take the terms sleep…sleeping horse…man; to illustrate the
latter take the terms sleep…waking horse…man。
Similar results will obtain if one of the terms is related
universally to the middle; the other in part。 If both premisses are
affirmative; the conclusion will be problematic; not pure; and also
when one premiss is negative; the other affirmative; the latter
being necessary。 But when the negative premiss is necessary; the
conclusion also will be a pure negative proposition; for the same kind
of proof can be given whether the terms are universal or not。 For
the syllogisms must be made perfect by means of the first figure; so
that a result which follows in the first figure follows also in the
third。 But when the minor premiss is negative and uni