prior analytics-第11章
按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!
terms。 Clearly then; if both the premisses are problematic; no
syllogism results。
18
But if one premiss is assertoric; the other problematic; if the
affirmative is assertoric and the negative problematic no syllogism
will be possible; whether the premisses are universal or particular。
The proof is the same as above; and by means of the same terms。 But
when the affirmative premiss is problematic; and the negative
assertoric; we shall have a syllogism。 Suppose A belongs to no B;
but can belong to all C。 If the negative proposition is converted; B
will belong to no A。 But ex hypothesi can belong to all C: so a
syllogism is made; proving by means of the first figure that B may
belong to no C。 Similarly also if the minor premiss is negative。 But
if both premisses are negative; one being assertoric; the other
problematic; nothing follows necessarily from these premisses as
they stand; but if the problematic premiss is converted into its
complementary affirmative a syllogism is formed to prove that B may
belong to no C; as before: for we shall again have the first figure。
But if both premisses are affirmative; no syllogism will be
possible。 This arrangement of terms is possible both when the relation
is positive; e。g。 health; animal; man; and when it is negative; e。g。
health; horse; man。
The same will hold good if the syllogisms are particular。 Whenever
the affirmative proposition is assertoric; whether universal or
particular; no syllogism is possible (this is proved similarly and
by the same examples as above); but when the negative proposition is
assertoric; a conclusion can be drawn by means of conversion; as
before。 Again if both the relations are negative; and the assertoric
proposition is universal; although no conclusion follows from the
actual premisses; a syllogism can be obtained by converting the
problematic premiss into its complementary affirmative as before。
But if the negative proposition is assertoric; but particular; no
syllogism is possible; whether the other premiss is affirmative or
negative。 Nor can a conclusion be drawn when both premisses are
indefinite; whether affirmative or negative; or particular。 The
proof is the same and by the same terms。
19
If one of the premisses is necessary; the other problematic; then if
the negative is necessary a syllogistic conclusion can be drawn; not
merely a negative problematic but also a negative assertoric
conclusion; but if the affirmative premiss is necessary; no conclusion
is possible。 Suppose that A necessarily belongs to no B; but may
belong to all C。 If the negative premiss is converted B will belong to
no A: but A ex hypothesi is capable of belonging to all C: so once
more a conclusion is drawn by the first figure that B may belong to no
C。 But at the same time it is clear that B will not belong to any C。
For assume that it does: then if A cannot belong to any B; and B
belongs to some of the Cs; A cannot belong to some of the Cs: but ex
hypothesi it may belong to all。 A similar proof can be given if the
minor premiss is negative。 Again let the affirmative proposition be
necessary; and the other problematic; i。e。 suppose that A may belong
to no B; but necessarily belongs to all C。 When the terms are arranged
in this way; no syllogism is possible。 For (1) it sometimes turns
out that B necessarily does not belong to C。 Let A be white; B man;
C swan。 White then necessarily belongs to swan; but may belong to no
man; and man necessarily belongs to no swan; Clearly then we cannot
draw a problematic conclusion; for that which is necessary is
admittedly distinct from that which is possible。 (2) Nor again can
we draw a necessary conclusion: for that presupposes that both
premisses are necessary; or at any rate the negative premiss。 (3)
Further it is possible also; when the terms are so arranged; that B
should belong to C: for nothing prevents C falling under B; A being
possible for all B; and necessarily belonging to C; e。g。 if C stands
for 'awake'; B for 'animal'; A for 'motion'。 For motion necessarily
belongs to what is awake; and is possible for every animal: and
everything that is awake is animal。 Clearly then the conclusion cannot
be the negative assertion; if the relation must be positive when the
terms are related as above。 Nor can the opposite affirmations be
established: consequently no syllogism is possible。 A similar proof is
possible if the major premiss is affirmative。
But if the premisses are similar in quality; when they are
negative a syllogism can always be formed by converting the
problematic premiss into its complementary affirmative as before。
Suppose A necessarily does not belong to B; and possibly may not
belong to C: if the premisses are converted B belongs to no A; and A
may possibly belong to all C: thus we have the first figure。 Similarly
if the minor premiss is negative。 But if the premisses are affirmative
there cannot be a syllogism。 Clearly the conclusion cannot be a
negative assertoric or a negative necessary proposition because no
negative premiss has been laid down either in the assertoric or in the
necessary mode。 Nor can the conclusion be a problematic negative
proposition。 For if the terms are so related; there are cases in which
B necessarily will not belong to C; e。g。 suppose that A is white; B
swan; C man。 Nor can the opposite affirmations be established; since
we have shown a case in which B necessarily does not belong to C。 A
syllogism then is not possible at all。
Similar relations will obtain in particular syllogisms。 For whenever
the negative proposition is universal and necessary; a syllogism
will always be possible to prove both a problematic and a negative
assertoric proposition (the proof proceeds by conversion); but when
the affirmative proposition is universal and necessary; no syllogistic
conclusion can be drawn。 This can be proved in the same way as for
universal propositions; and by the same terms。 Nor is a syllogistic
conclusion possible when both premisses are affirmative: this also may
be proved as above。 But when both premisses are negative; and the
premiss that definitely disconnects two terms is universal and
necessary; though nothing follows necessarily from the premisses as
they are stated; a conclusion can be drawn as above if the problematic
premiss is converted into its complementary affirmative。 But if both
are indefinite or particular; no syllogism can be formed。 The same
proof will serve; and the same terms。
It is clear then from what has been said that if the universal and
negative premiss is necessary; a syllogism is always possible; proving
not merely a negative problematic; but also a negative assertoric
proposition; but if the affirmative premiss is necessary no conclusion
can be drawn。 It is clear too that a syllogism is possible or not
under the same conditions whether the mode of the premisses is
assertoric or necessary。 And it is clear that all the syllogisms are
imperfect; and are completed by means of the figures mentioned。
20
In the last figure a syllogism is possible whether both or only
one of the premisses is problematic。 When the premisses are
problematic the conclusion will be problematic; and also when one
premiss is problematic; the other assertoric。 But when the other
premiss is necessary; if it is affirmative the conclusion will be
neither necessary or ass