贝壳电子书 > 英文原著电子书 > prior analytics >

第10章

prior analytics-第10章

小说: prior analytics 字数: 每页4000字

按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!






negative proposition is necessary; the conclusion will be negative



assertoric: e。g。 if it is not possible that A should belong to any



B; but B may belong to some of the Cs; it is necessary that A should



not belong to some of the Cs。 For if A belongs to all C; but cannot



belong to any B; neither can B belong to any A。 So if A belongs to all



C; to none of the Cs can B belong。 But it was laid down that B may



belong to some C。 But when the particular affirmative in the



negative syllogism; e。g。 BC the minor premiss; or the universal



proposition in the affirmative syllogism; e。g。 AB the major premiss;



is necessary; there will not be an assertoric conclusion。 The



demonstration is the same as before。 But if the minor premiss is



universal; and problematic; whether affirmative or negative; and the



major premiss is particular and necessary; there cannot be a



syllogism。 Premisses of this kind are possible both where the relation



is positive and necessary; e。g。 animal…white…man; and where it is



necessary and negative; e。g。 animal…white…garment。 But when the



universal is necessary; the particular problematic; if the universal



is negative we may take the terms animal…white…raven to illustrate the



positive relation; or animal…white…pitch to illustrate the negative;



and if the universal is affirmative we may take the terms



animal…white…swan to illustrate the positive relation; and



animal…white…snow to illustrate the negative and necessary relation。



Nor again is a syllogism possible when the premisses are indefinite;



or both particular。 Terms applicable in either case to illustrate



the positive relation are animal…white…man: to illustrate the



negative; animal…white…inanimate。 For the relation of animal to some



white; and of white to some inanimate; is both necessary and



positive and necessary and negative。 Similarly if the relation is



problematic: so the terms may be used for all cases。



  Clearly then from what has been said a syllogism results or not from



similar relations of the terms whether we are dealing with simple



existence or necessity; with this exception; that if the negative



premiss is assertoric the conclusion is problematic; but if the



negative premiss is necessary the conclusion is both problematic and



negative assertoric。 'It is clear also that all the syllogisms are



imperfect and are perfected by means of the figures above mentioned。'







                                17







  In the second figure whenever both premisses are problematic; no



syllogism is possible; whether the premisses are affirmative or



negative; universal or particular。 But when one premiss is assertoric;



the other problematic; if the affirmative is assertoric no syllogism



is possible; but if the universal negative is assertoric a



conclusion can always be drawn。 Similarly when one premiss is



necessary; the other problematic。 Here also we must understand the



term 'possible' in the conclusion; in the same sense as before。



  First we must point out that the negative problematic proposition is



not convertible; e。g。 if A may belong to no B; it does not follow that



B may belong to no A。 For suppose it to follow and assume that B may



belong to no A。 Since then problematic affirmations are convertible



with negations; whether they are contraries or contradictories; and



since B may belong to no A; it is clear that B may belong to all A。



But this is false: for if all this can be that; it does not follow



that all that can be this: consequently the negative proposition is



not convertible。 Further; these propositions are not incompatible;



'A may belong to no B'; 'B necessarily does not belong to some of



the As'; e。g。 it is possible that no man should be white (for it is



also possible that every man should be white); but it is not true to



say that it is possible that no white thing should be a man: for



many white things are necessarily not men; and the necessary (as we



saw) other than the possible。



  Moreover it is not possible to prove the convertibility of these



propositions by a reductio ad absurdum; i。e。 by claiming assent to the



following argument: 'since it is false that B may belong to no A; it



is true that it cannot belong to no A; for the one statement is the



contradictory of the other。 But if this is so; it is true that B



necessarily belongs to some of the As: consequently A necessarily



belongs to some of the Bs。 But this is impossible。' The argument



cannot be admitted; for it does not follow that some A is



necessarily B; if it is not possible that no A should be B。 For the



latter expression is used in two senses; one if A some is



necessarily B; another if some A is necessarily not B。 For it is not



true to say that that which necessarily does not belong to some of the



As may possibly not belong to any A; just as it is not true to say



that what necessarily belongs to some A may possibly belong to all



A。 If any one then should claim that because it is not possible for



C to belong to all D; it necessarily does not belong to some D; he



would make a false assumption: for it does belong to all D; but



because in some cases it belongs necessarily; therefore we say that it



is not possible for it to belong to all。 Hence both the propositions



'A necessarily belongs to some B' and 'A necessarily does not belong



to some B' are opposed to the proposition 'A belongs to all B'。



Similarly also they are opposed to the proposition 'A may belong to no



B'。 It is clear then that in relation to what is possible and not



possible; in the sense originally defined; we must assume; not that



A necessarily belongs to some B; but that A necessarily does not



belong to some B。 But if this is assumed; no absurdity results:



consequently no syllogism。 It is clear from what has been said that



the negative proposition is not convertible。



  This being proved; suppose it possible that A may belong to no B and



to all C。 By means of conversion no syllogism will result: for the



major premiss; as has been said; is not convertible。 Nor can a proof



be obtained by a reductio ad absurdum: for if it is assumed that B can



belong to all C; no false consequence results: for A may belong both



to all C and to no C。 In general; if there is a syllogism; it is clear



that its conclusion will be problematic because neither of the



premisses is assertoric; and this must be either affirmative or



negative。 But neither is possible。 Suppose the conclusion is



affirmative: it will be proved by an example that the predicate cannot



belong to the subject。 Suppose the conclusion is negative: it will



be proved that it is not problematic but necessary。 Let A be white;



B man; C horse。 It is possible then for A to belong to all of the



one and to none of the other。 But it is not possible for B to belong



nor not to belong to C。 That it is not possible for it to belong; is



clear。 For no horse is a man。 Neither is it possible for it not to



belong。 For it is necessary that no horse should be a man; but the



necessary we found to be different from the possible。 No syllogism



then results。 A similar proof can be given if the major premiss is



negative; the minor affirmative; or if both are affirmative or



negative。 The demonstration can be made by means of the same terms。



And whenever one premiss is universal; the other particular; or both



are particular or indefinite; or in whatever other way the premisses



can be altered; the proof will always proceed through the same



terms。 Clearly then; if both the premisses are problematic; no



syllogism results。







  

返回目录 上一页 下一页 回到顶部 0 0

你可能喜欢的