a theologico-political treatise [part iv]-第5章
按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!
natural right。 (105) For the civil right is dependent on his own decree; and
natural right is dependent on the laws of nature; which latter are not
adapted to religion; whose sole aim is the good of humanity; but to the
order of nature … that is; to God's eternal decree unknown to us。
(16:106) This truth seems to be adumbrated in a somewhat obscurer form by
those who maintain that men can sin against God's revelation; but not
against the eternal decree by which He has ordained all things。
(107) We may be asked; what should we do if the sovereign commands anything
contrary to religion; and the obedience which we have expressly vowed to
God? should we obey the Divine law or the human law? (108) I shall treat of
this question at length hereafter; and will therefore merely say now; that
God should be obeyed before all else; when we have a certain and
indisputable revelation of His will: but men are very prone to error on
religious subjects; and; according to the diversity of their dispositions;
are wont with considerable stir to put forward their own inventions; as
experience more than sufficiently attests; so that if no one were bound to
obey the state in matters which; in his own opinion concern religion;
the rights of the state would be dependent on every man's judgment
and passions。 (109) No one would consider himself bound to obey laws framed
against his faith or superstition; and on this pretext he might assume
unbounded license。 (110) In this way; the rights of the civil authorities
would be utterly set at nought; so that we must conclude that the sovereign
power; which alone is bound both by Divine and natural right to preserve and
guard the laws of the state; should have supreme authority for making any
laws about religion which it thinks fit; all are bound to obey its behests
on the subject in accordance with their promise which God bids them to keep。
(16:111) However; if the sovereign power be heathen; we should either enter
into no engagements therewith; and yield up our lives sooner than transfer
to it any of our rights; or; if the engagement be made; and our rights
transferred; we should (inasmuch as we should have ourselves transferred the
right of defending ourselves and our religion) be bound to obey them; and to
keep our word: we might even rightly be bound so to do; except in those
cases where God; by indisputable revelation; has promised His special aid
against tyranny; or given us special exemption from obedience。 (112) Thus we
see that; of all the Jews in Babylon; there were only three youths who were
certain of the help of God; and; therefore; refused to obey Nebuchadnezzar。
(113) All the rest; with the sole exception of Daniel; who was beloved by
the king; were doubtless compelled by right to obey; perhaps thinking that
they had been delivered up by God into the hands of the king; and that the
king had obtained and preserved his dominion by God's design。 (114) On the
other hand; Eleazar; before his country had utterly fallen; wished to give a
proof of his constancy to his compatriots; in order that they might follow
in his footsteps; and go to any lengths; rather than allow their right and
power to be transferred to the Greeks; or brave any torture rather than
swear allegiance to the heathen。 (115) Instances are occurring every day in
confirmation of what I here advance。 (116) The rulers of Christian
kingdoms do not hesitate; with a view to strengthening their dominion; to
make treaties with Turks and heathen; and to give orders to their subjects
who settle among such peoples not to assume more freedom; either in
things secular or religious; than is set down in the treaty; or allowed by
the foreign government。 (117) We may see this exemplified in the Dutch
treaty with the Japanese; which I have already mentioned。
'17:0' CHAPTER XVII … IT IS SHOWN THAT NO ONE CAN; OR
NEED; TRANSFER ALL HIS RIGHTS TO THE SOVEREIGN POWER。
OF THE HEBREW REPUBLIC; AS IT WAS DURING THE LIFETIME
OF MOSES; AND AFTER HIS DEATH; TILL THE FOUNDATION
OF THE MONARCHY; AND OF ITS EXCELLENCE。 LASTLY; OF
THE CAUSES WHY THE THEOCRATIC REPUBLIC FELL; AND WHY
IT COULD HARDLY HAVE CONTINUED WITHOUT DISSENSION。
'17:1' (1) The theory put forward in the last chapter; of the universal
rights of the sovereign power; and of the natural rights of the individual
transferred thereto; though it corresponds in many respects with actual
practice; and though practice may be so arranged as to conform to it more
and more; must nevertheless always remain in many respects purely ideal。 (2)
No one can ever so utterly transfer to another his power and; consequently;
his rights; as to cease to be a man; nor can there ever be a power so
sovereign that it can carry out every possible wish。 (3) It will always be
vain to order a subject to hate what he believes brings him advantage; or to
love what brings him loss; or not to be offended at insults; or not to wish
to be free from fear; or a hundred other things of the sort; which
necessarily follow from the laws of human nature。 (4) So much; I think; is
abundantly shown by experience: for men have never so far ceded their power
as to cease to be an object of fear to the rulers who received such power
and right; and dominions have always been in as much danger from their own
subjects as from external enemies。 (5) If it were really the case; that men
could be deprived of their natural rights so utterly as never to have any
further influence on affairs 'Endnote 29'; except with the permission of the
holders of sovereign right; it would then be possible to maintain with
impunity the most violent tyranny; which; I suppose; no one would for an
instant admit。
(17:6) We must; therefore; grant that every man retains some part of his
right; in dependence on his own decision; and no one else's。
(7) However; in order correctly to understand the extent of the sovereign's
right and power; we must take notice that it does not cover only those
actions to which it can compel men by fear; but absolutely every action
which it can induce men to perform: for it is the fact of obedience; not the
motive for obedience; which makes a man a subject。
(17:8) Whatever be the cause which leads a man to obey the commands of the
sovereign; whether it be fear or hope; or love of his country; or any other
emotion … the fact remains that the man takes counsel with himself; and
nevertheless acts as his sovereign orders。 (9) We must not; therefore;
assert that all actions resulting from a man's deliberation with himself are
done in obedience to the rights of the individual rather than the sovereign:
as a matter of fact; all actions spring from a man's deliberation with
himself; whether the determining motive be love or fear of punishment;
therefore; either dominion does not exist; and has no rights over its
subjects; or else it extends over every instance in which it can prevail on
men to decide to obey it。 (10) Consequently; every action which a subject
performs in accordance with the commands of the sovereign; whether such
action springs from love; or fear; or (as is more frequently the case) from
hope and fear together; or from reverence。 compounded of fear and
admiration; or; indeed; any motive whatever; is performed in virtue of his
submission to the sovereign; and not in virtue of his own authority。
(17:11) This point is made still more clear by the fact that obedience does
not consist so much in the outward act as in the mental state of the person
obeying; so that he is most under the dominion of another who with his whole
heart determines to obey another's commands; and consequently the firmest
dominion belongs to the sovereign who has most influence ove