posterior analytics-第4章
按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!
that is to be taken to mean that it is true of a given subject
primarily and as such。 Case (3) may be thus exemplified。 If a proof
were given that perpendiculars to the same line are parallel; it might
be supposed that lines thus perpendicular were the proper subject of
the demonstration because being parallel is true of every instance
of them。 But it is not so; for the parallelism depends not on these
angles being equal to one another because each is a right angle; but
simply on their being equal to one another。 An example of (1) would be
as follows: if isosceles were the only triangle; it would be thought
to have its angles equal to two right angles qua isosceles。 An
instance of (2) would be the law that proportionals alternate。
Alternation used to be demonstrated separately of numbers; lines;
solids; and durations; though it could have been proved of them all by
a single demonstration。 Because there was no single name to denote
that in which numbers; lengths; durations; and solids are identical;
and because they differed specifically from one another; this property
was proved of each of them separately。 To…day; however; the proof is
commensurately universal; for they do not possess this attribute qua
lines or qua numbers; but qua manifesting this generic character which
they are postulated as possessing universally。 Hence; even if one
prove of each kind of triangle that its angles are equal to two
right angles; whether by means of the same or different proofs; still;
as long as one treats separately equilateral; scalene; and
isosceles; one does not yet know; except sophistically; that
triangle has its angles equal to two right angles; nor does one yet
know that triangle has this property commensurately and universally;
even if there is no other species of triangle but these。 For one
does not know that triangle as such has this property; nor even that
'all' triangles have it…unless 'all' means 'each taken singly': if
'all' means 'as a whole class'; then; though there be none in which
one does not recognize this property; one does not know it of 'all
triangles'。
When; then; does our knowledge fail of commensurate universality;
and when it is unqualified knowledge? If triangle be identical in
essence with equilateral; i。e。 with each or all equilaterals; then
clearly we have unqualified knowledge: if on the other hand it be not;
and the attribute belongs to equilateral qua triangle; then our
knowledge fails of commensurate universality。 'But'; it will be asked;
'does this attribute belong to the subject of which it has been
demonstrated qua triangle or qua isosceles? What is the point at which
the subject。 to which it belongs is primary? (i。e。 to what subject can
it be demonstrated as belonging commensurately and universally?)'
Clearly this point is the first term in which it is found to inhere as
the elimination of inferior differentiae proceeds。 Thus the angles
of a brazen isosceles triangle are equal to two right angles: but
eliminate brazen and isosceles and the attribute remains。 'But'…you
may say…'eliminate figure or limit; and the attribute vanishes。' True;
but figure and limit are not the first differentiae whose
elimination destroys the attribute。 'Then what is the first?' If it is
triangle; it will be in virtue of triangle that the attribute
belongs to all the other subjects of which it is predicable; and
triangle is the subject to which it can be demonstrated as belonging
commensurately and universally。
6
Demonstrative knowledge must rest on necessary basic truths; for the
object of scientific knowledge cannot be other than it is。 Now
attributes attaching essentially to their subjects attach
necessarily to them: for essential attributes are either elements in
the essential nature of their subjects; or contain their subjects as
elements in their own essential nature。 (The pairs of opposites
which the latter class includes are necessary because one member or
the other necessarily inheres。) It follows from this that premisses of
the demonstrative syllogism must be connexions essential in the
sense explained: for all attributes must inhere essentially or else be
accidental; and accidental attributes are not necessary to their
subjects。
We must either state the case thus; or else premise that the
conclusion of demonstration is necessary and that a demonstrated
conclusion cannot be other than it is; and then infer that the
conclusion must be developed from necessary premisses。 For though
you may reason from true premisses without demonstrating; yet if
your premisses are necessary you will assuredly demonstrate…in such
necessity you have at once a distinctive character of demonstration。
That demonstration proceeds from necessary premisses is also indicated
by the fact that the objection we raise against a professed
demonstration is that a premiss of it is not a necessary truth…whether
we think it altogether devoid of necessity; or at any rate so far as
our opponent's previous argument goes。 This shows how naive it is to
suppose one's basic truths rightly chosen if one starts with a
proposition which is (1) popularly accepted and (2) true; such as
the sophists' assumption that to know is the same as to possess
knowledge。 For (1) popular acceptance or rejection is no criterion
of a basic truth; which can only be the primary law of the genus
constituting the subject matter of the demonstration; and (2) not
all truth is 'appropriate'。
A further proof that the conclusion must be the development of
necessary premisses is as follows。 Where demonstration is possible;
one who can give no account which includes the cause has no scientific
knowledge。 If; then; we suppose a syllogism in which; though A
necessarily inheres in C; yet B; the middle term of the demonstration;
is not necessarily connected with A and C; then the man who argues
thus has no reasoned knowledge of the conclusion; since this
conclusion does not owe its necessity to the middle term; for though
the conclusion is necessary; the mediating link is a contingent
fact。 Or again; if a man is without knowledge now; though he still
retains the steps of the argument; though there is no change in
himself or in the fact and no lapse of memory on his part; then
neither had he knowledge previously。 But the mediating link; not being
necessary; may have perished in the interval; and if so; though
there be no change in him nor in the fact; and though he will still
retain the steps of the argument; yet he has not knowledge; and
therefore had not knowledge before。 Even if the link has not
actually perished but is liable to perish; this situation is
possible and might occur。 But such a condition cannot be knowledge。
When the conclusion is necessary; the middle through which it was
proved may yet quite easily be non…necessary。 You can in fact infer
the necessary even from a non…necessary premiss; just as you can infer
the true from the not true。 On the other hand; when the middle is
necessary the conclusion must be necessary; just as true premisses
always give a true conclusion。 Thus; if A is necessarily predicated of
B and B of C; then A is necessarily predicated of C。 But when the
conclusion is nonnecessary the middle cannot be necessary either。
Thus: let A be predicated non…necessarily of C but necessarily of B;
and let B be a necessary predicate of C; then A too will be a
necessary predicate of C; which by hypothesis it is not。
To sum