贝壳电子书 > 英文原著电子书 > posterior analytics >

第13章

posterior analytics-第13章

小说: posterior analytics 字数: 每页4000字

按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!






and these cannot be infinite; the ascending series will terminate; and



consequently the descending series too。



  If this is so; it follows that the intermediates between any two



terms are also always limited in number。 An immediately obvious



consequence of this is that demonstrations necessarily involve basic



truths; and that the contention of some…referred to at the outset…that



all truths are demonstrable is mistaken。 For if there are basic



truths; (a) not all truths are demonstrable; and (b) an infinite



regress is impossible; since if either (a) or (b) were not a fact;



it would mean that no interval was immediate and indivisible; but that



all intervals were divisible。 This is true because a conclusion is



demonstrated by the interposition; not the apposition; of a fresh



term。 If such interposition could continue to infinity there might



be an infinite number of terms between any two terms; but this is



impossible if both the ascending and descending series of



predication terminate; and of this fact; which before was shown



dialectically; analytic proof has now been given。







                                23







  It is an evident corollary of these conclusions that if the same



attribute A inheres in two terms C and D predicable either not at all;



or not of all instances; of one another; it does not always belong



to them in virtue of a common middle term。 Isosceles and scalene



possess the attribute of having their angles equal to two right angles



in virtue of a common middle; for they possess it in so far as they



are both a certain kind of figure; and not in so far as they differ



from one another。 But this is not always the case: for; were it so; if



we take B as the common middle in virtue of which A inheres in C and



D; clearly B would inhere in C and D through a second common middle;



and this in turn would inhere in C and D through a third; so that



between two terms an infinity of intermediates would fall…an



impossibility。 Thus it need not always be in virtue of a common middle



term that a single attribute inheres in several subjects; since



there must be immediate intervals。 Yet if the attribute to be proved



common to two subjects is to be one of their essential attributes; the



middle terms involved must be within one subject genus and be



derived from the same group of immediate premisses; for we have seen



that processes of proof cannot pass from one genus to another。



  It is also clear that when A inheres in B; this can be



demonstrated if there is a middle term。 Further; the 'elements' of



such a conclusion are the premisses containing the middle in question;



and they are identical in number with the middle terms; seeing that



the immediate propositions…or at least such immediate propositions



as are universal…are the 'elements'。 If; on the other hand; there is



no middle term; demonstration ceases to be possible: we are on the way



to the basic truths。 Similarly if A does not inhere in B; this can



be demonstrated if there is a middle term or a term prior to B in



which A does not inhere: otherwise there is no demonstration and a



basic truth is reached。 There are; moreover; as many 'elements' of the



demonstrated conclusion as there are middle terms; since it is



propositions containing these middle terms that are the basic



premisses on which the demonstration rests; and as there are some



indemonstrable basic truths asserting that 'this is that' or that



'this inheres in that'; so there are others denying that 'this is



that' or that 'this inheres in that'…in fact some basic truths will



affirm and some will deny being。



  When we are to prove a conclusion; we must take a primary



essential predicate…suppose it C…of the subject B; and then suppose



A similarly predicable of C。 If we proceed in this manner; no



proposition or attribute which falls beyond A is admitted in the



proof: the interval is constantly condensed until subject and



predicate become indivisible; i。e。 one。 We have our unit when the



premiss becomes immediate; since the immediate premiss alone is a



single premiss in the unqualified sense of 'single'。 And as in other



spheres the basic element is simple but not identical in all…in a



system of weight it is the mina; in music the quarter…tone; and so



onso in syllogism the unit is an immediate premiss; and in the



knowledge that demonstration gives it is an intuition。 In



syllogisms; then; which prove the inherence of an attribute; nothing



falls outside the major term。 In the case of negative syllogisms on



the other hand; (1) in the first figure nothing falls outside the



major term whose inherence is in question; e。g。 to prove through a



middle C that A does not inhere in B the premisses required are; all B



is C; no C is A。 Then if it has to be proved that no C is A; a



middle must be found between and C; and this procedure will never



vary。



  (2) If we have to show that E is not D by means of the premisses;



all D is C; no E; or not all E; is C; then the middle will never



fall beyond E; and E is the subject of which D is to be denied in



the conclusion。



  (3) In the third figure the middle will never fall beyond the limits



of the subject and the attribute denied of it。







                                24







  Since demonstrations may be either commensurately universal or



particular; and either affirmative or negative; the question arises;



which form is the better? And the same question may be put in regard



to so…called 'direct' demonstration and reductio ad impossibile。 Let



us first examine the commensurately universal and the particular



forms; and when we have cleared up this problem proceed to discuss



'direct' demonstration and reductio ad impossibile。



  The following considerations might lead some minds to prefer



particular demonstration。



  (1) The superior demonstration is the demonstration which gives us



greater knowledge (for this is the ideal of demonstration); and we



have greater knowledge of a particular individual when we know it in



itself than when we know it through something else; e。g。 we know



Coriscus the musician better when we know that Coriscus is musical



than when we know only that man is musical; and a like argument



holds in all other cases。 But commensurately universal



demonstration; instead of proving that the subject itself actually



is x; proves only that something else is x… e。g。 in attempting to



prove that isosceles is x; it proves not that isosceles but only that



triangle is x… whereas particular demonstration proves that the



subject itself is x。 The demonstration; then; that a subject; as such;



possesses an attribute is superior。 If this is so; and if the



particular rather than the commensurately universal forms



demonstrates; particular demonstration is superior。



  (2) The universal has not a separate being over against groups of



singulars。 Demonstration nevertheless creates the opinion that its



function is conditioned by something like this…some separate entity



belonging to the real world; that; for instance; of triangle or of



figure or number; over against particular triangles; figures; and



numbers。 But demonstration which touches the real and will not mislead



is superior to that which moves among unrealities and is delusory。 Now



commensurately universal demonstration is of the latter kind: if we



engage in it we find ourselves reasoning after a fashion well



illustrated by the argument that the proportionate is what answers



to the definition of some entity which is neither line; number; solid;

返回目录 上一页 下一页 回到顶部 2 2

你可能喜欢的