贝壳电子书 > 英文原著电子书 > posterior analytics >

第11章

posterior analytics-第11章

小说: posterior analytics 字数: 每页4000字

按键盘上方向键 ← 或 → 可快速上下翻页,按键盘上的 Enter 键可回到本书目录页,按键盘上方向键 ↑ 可回到本页顶部!
————未阅读完?加入书签已便下次继续阅读!






conclusions and premisses: viz。 if A is attributable to no B; then



either this predication will be primary; or there will be an



intermediate term prior to B to which a is not attributable…G; let



us say; which is attributable to all B…and there may still be



another term H prior to G; which is attributable to all G。 The same



questions arise; I say; because in these cases too either the series



of prior terms to which a is not attributable is infinite or it



terminates。



  One cannot ask the same questions in the case of reciprocating



terms; since when subject and predicate are convertible there is





neither primary nor ultimate subject; seeing that all the



reciprocals qua subjects stand in the same relation to one another;



whether we say that the subject has an infinity of attributes or



that both subjects and attributes…and we raised the question in both



cases…are infinite in number。 These questions then cannot be



asked…unless; indeed; the terms can reciprocate by two different



modes; by accidental predication in one relation and natural



predication in the other。







                                20







  Now; it is clear that if the predications terminate in both the



upward and the downward direction (by 'upward' I mean the ascent to



the more universal; by 'downward' the descent to the more particular);



the middle terms cannot be infinite in number。 For suppose that A is



predicated of F; and that the intermediates…call them BB'B〃。。。…are



infinite; then clearly you might descend from and find one term



predicated of another ad infinitum; since you have an infinity of



terms between you and F; and equally; if you ascend from F; there



are infinite terms between you and A。 It follows that if these



processes are impossible there cannot be an infinity of



intermediates between A and F。 Nor is it of any effect to urge that



some terms of the series AB。。。F are contiguous so as to exclude



intermediates; while others cannot be taken into the argument at



all: whichever terms of the series B。。。I take; the number of



intermediates in the direction either of A or of F must be finite or



infinite: where the infinite series starts; whether from the first



term or from a later one; is of no moment; for the succeeding terms in



any case are infinite in number。







                                21







  Further; if in affirmative demonstration the series terminates in



both directions; clearly it will terminate too in negative



demonstration。 Let us assume that we cannot proceed to infinity either



by ascending from the ultimate term (by 'ultimate term' I mean a



term such as was; not itself attributable to a subject but itself



the subject of attributes); or by descending towards an ultimate



from the primary term (by 'primary term' I mean a term predicable of a



subject but not itself a subject)。 If this assumption is justified;



the series will also terminate in the case of negation。 For a negative



conclusion can be proved in all three figures。 In the first figure



it is proved thus: no B is A; all C is B。 In packing the interval



B…C we must reach immediate propositionsas is always the case with



the minor premisssince B…C is affirmative。 As regards the other



premiss it is plain that if the major term is denied of a term D prior



to B; D will have to be predicable of all B; and if the major is



denied of yet another term prior to D; this term must be predicable of



all D。 Consequently; since the ascending series is finite; the descent



will also terminate and there will be a subject of which A is



primarily non…predicable。 In the second figure the syllogism is; all A



is B; no C is B;。。no C is A。 If proof of this is required; plainly



it may be shown either in the first figure as above; in the second



as here; or in the third。 The first figure has been discussed; and



we will proceed to display the second; proof by which will be as



follows: all B is D; no C is D。。。; since it is required that B



should be a subject of which a predicate is affirmed。 Next; since D is



to be proved not to belong to C; then D has a further predicate



which is denied of C。 Therefore; since the succession of predicates



affirmed of an ever higher universal terminates; the succession of



predicates denied terminates too。



  The third figure shows it as follows: all B is A; some B is not C。



Therefore some A is not C。 This premiss; i。e。 C…B; will be proved



either in the same figure or in one of the two figures discussed



above。 In the first and second figures the series terminates。 If we



use the third figure; we shall take as premisses; all E is B; some E



is not C; and this premiss again will be proved by a similar



prosyllogism。 But since it is assumed that the series of descending



subjects also terminates; plainly the series of more universal



non…predicables will terminate also。 Even supposing that the proof



is not confined to one method; but employs them all and is now in



the first figure; now in the second or third…even so the regress



will terminate; for the methods are finite in number; and if finite



things are combined in a finite number of ways; the result must be



finite。



  Thus it is plain that the regress of middles terminates in the



case of negative demonstration; if it does so also in the case of



affirmative demonstration。 That in fact the regress terminates in both



these cases may be made clear by the following dialectical



considerations。







                                22







  In the case of predicates constituting the essential nature of a



thing; it clearly terminates; seeing that if definition is possible;



or in other words; if essential form is knowable; and an infinite



series cannot be traversed; predicates constituting a thing's



essential nature must be finite in number。 But as regards predicates



generally we have the following prefatory remarks to make。 (1) We



can affirm without falsehood 'the white (thing) is walking'; and



that big (thing) is a log'; or again; 'the log is big'; and 'the man



walks'。 But the affirmation differs in the two cases。 When I affirm



'the white is a log'; I mean that something which happens to be



white is a log…not that white is the substratum in which log



inheres; for it was not qua white or qua a species of white that the



white (thing) came to be a log; and the white (thing) is



consequently not a log except incidentally。 On the other hand; when



I affirm 'the log is white'; I do not mean that something else;



which happens also to be a log; is white (as I should if I said 'the



musician is white;' which would mean 'the man who happens also to be a



musician is white'); on the contrary; log is here the substratum…the



substratum which actually came to be white; and did so qua wood or qua



a species of wood and qua nothing else。



  If we must lay down a rule; let us entitle the latter kind of



statement predication; and the former not predication at all; or not



strict but accidental predication。 'White' and 'log' will thus serve



as types respectively of predicate and subject。



  We shall assume; then; that the predicate is invariably predicated



strictly and not accidentally of the subject; for on such



predication demonstrations depend for their force。 It follows from



this that when a single attribute is predicated of a single subject;



the predicate must affirm of the subject either some element



constituting its essential nature; or that it is in some way



qualified; quantified; essentially related; active; passive; placed;



or dated。

返回目录 上一页 下一页 回到顶部 2 2

你可能喜欢的